The Question of Being
Let us now look at the rest of the introduction ofย Being and Timeย having understood and grasped the importance of the phenomenological method to its overall argument. Introductions are always the most difficult to comprehend in any book, because they already presuppose that we know what is being investigated. Here the author informs us what the book is about, but we as readers might be entirely in the dark, so much so that we might not even understand why the book was written in theย first place. Secondly, it is in the introduction that the author will lay on the table, for theย first time, the tools through which the investigation will proceed. In philosophy, this is usually the technical vocabulary with which any research is possible. The difficulty of making sense of these words is only further compounded if the author is attempting to make an original contribution, for then they are likely to have to invent new words in order that we can see the problem in a original way, rather than relying on our learned knowledge, or even ignorance. Of course, it is up to us as readers to decide if this originality is worth it or not. Both these issues are visible in the introduction toย Being and Time. First of all, we are not at all sure what Heidegger means by the question of Being, and even whether it is worthwhile, and secondly he will throw into theseย first pages a lot of special terminology which we will never have encountered before. It is no surprise, therefore, that many readers never get beyond theseย first few pages, or will complain that Heidegger is an unnecessarily difficult and impenetrable writer.
Having said this, however, philosophy, even though it might always push at the limits of language, is always about the simplest matters.
Unfortunately what is simple can be the most difficult to understand. For Heidegger, the question of Being is not a technical question which only the cleverest people can ask who have had many years of train- ing in philosophy. On the contrary, we all already have an under- standing of Being, even if we do not know how to put it into words. In this chapter, we will examine in detail the rest of the introduction toย Being and Timeย (we only looked at the section on phenomenology in the introduction) and it is divided into three sections. Theย first explains why Heidegger thinks the question of Being has been for- gotten and what the difference between beings and Being is (even if the latter can only be done in the most perfunctory and incomplete way, since this difference is the very problem of Heideggerโs thought and not only inย Being and Time). The second investigates why, in rela- tion to the question of Being (as I ended in the introduction) Dasein has a fundamental priority for Heidegger, and why also, as we shall see in the third section, this necessitates what he calls the โdestruction of the history of ontologyโ. Finally, we will conclude with what the overall aim ofย Being and Timeย as a whole is, and how the structure of the book reflects Heideggerโs intentions, or even fails to do so.
From Beings to Being
Heidegger, in the opening pages ofย Being and Time, wants us to feel the very strangeness and peculiarity of the question of Being. Like the stranger in Platoโsย Sophist, which he quotes in the exergue, we thought we knew what this question meant, but now we are no longer sure (BT: 1). Our position is doubly difficult. Not only do we not know the answer to the question, we do not even know how to ask the question properly or even what the question is asking us. There are good his- torical reasons, which we shall come to in the third section of this chapter, why we are so perplexed, but we must all start with some understanding of Being, otherwise there would be nowhere to begin at all. It is just that our own presuppositions and assumptions get in the way of us seeing what is there before us.
Let us then start with our ordinary understanding of Being and see if this helps to get us beyond our initial confusion. All of us already use Being in our ordinary conversations. I say, โThe sky is very blue today.โ Already in this little word โisโ, I imply a meaning of Being, even if, were someone to ask, I would not be able to define it. I suppose if
I were going to make a stab at it, I would say โisโ means โexistsโ, and if I were going to give a very tortuous reply, I would say, โThe sky is very blue todayโ means โThere is something which is the sky that exists which is very blue today.โ But already in my explanation, which I know is very clumsy, there are two meanings of Being. One is the thing itself which I am talking about, the sky, and the other is the very fact of its existence. In German, this distinction is easy to make lin- guistically because it can be expressed by the grammatical difference between โbeingโ (Seiende), meaning a being, and โBeingโ (Sein), meaning existence. Already from the translation of these two words, we can see a problem: in English, we use the same word โbeingโ to describe the two different meanings. This is why most translators of Heidegger (as we have already been doing so far in this book) write โBeingโ with a capital to mean existence, and โbeingโ with a small โbโ to mean some- thing which exists.
Of course, there are many kinds of beings. A stone is a being, a mathematical formula is a being, and even you and I are beings. What is common to all these beings is that they exist โ they โareโ in some way. Obviously, they are not all in the same way. I am not in the same way that a stone is (or even an animal, Heidegger will say in a lecture he gave after he wroteย Being and Time),1ย and quite clearly I am not in the same way that a mathematical formula is. None the less, and this is what is so strange and peculiar about the question of Being, even though all these beings are in a different way we all agree that they are. What does the word โBeingโ mean such that I can use it of every- thing and yet it does really seem to say anything at all since it does not pick out any specific character of a being, like the property red or hard might do?
That there is not an easy and readily available answer to this ques- tion is not just because it is hard to answer, but also that the tradition handed down to us (which even has the name โontologyโ) makes it vir- tually impossible for us to do so. We do need, however, to be careful here. It is not that Heidegger just wants to damn the whole of our past. In fact he makes it clear that the question of Being is not โnewโ at all, but rather a very ancient question (BT: 40). His relation to the past is ambivalent. On the one hand, it prevents us from understand- ing the question of Being, but on the other, the only resources for renewing this question come from this past. What allows us to tease
open what is genuine in the past is always our own present experience of Being. The past is of no interest for Heidegger, if we mean by it simply facts and information about a bygone age. What counts is whether the past reveals to us who we are (why we are not the same as a stone, or a mathematical formula).
There is no doubt it is Aristotle more than any other philosopher who determines Heideggerโs approach to the question of Being. We might say that he has the same ambiguous relationship to him as we all have to the past. On the one hand, Aristotle is theย first philosopher to take the question of Being seriously as the fundamental question, and also there is no doubt that even the later analysis of Dasein is shaped by Heideggerโs reading of Aristotleโsย Nicomachean Ethics.2ย On the other hand, however, it is Aristotleโs setting out of the question of Being that has led to its being forgotten and neglected. This is why Heidegger can write of Aristotle that he โput the problem of Being on what was, in principle, a new basisโ (BT: 22), but at the same timeย Being and Timeย is aimed at overthrowing Aristotleโs conception of time as an adequate understanding of Being (BT: 48).3
How, then, does Aristotle understand Being? The key here is com- prehending what he means by definition, and why the meaning of Being is so problematic in relation to it. In Aristotleโs vocabulary, I define something byย first knowing what genus it belongs to and then what species within this genus. Thus, โmanโ belongs to the genus โanimalโ, and then by picking out what differentiates it from any other species in the genus, rationality, I can arrive at the definition, โratio- nal animalโ. Even Aristotle realised that such a process could not be used to explain the meaning of Being, because there is no specific difference which you could point to that would distinguish it from anything else (remember our initial discussion that I can say I am, a mathematical formula is, the sky is, and so on). As Magda King writes, I can explain the genus โanimalโ by pointing to a horse, but it would be strange to point to a horse and say, โThis is what I mean by โisโ.โ4ย How would you know what I was pointing at to determine Beingโs meaning? Its eyes, ears, legs, colour?
The reason why Being transcends every genus is that it is common to every being, but because the only way in which it can define things is by picking out specific differences, there does not seem to be any way in which to say anything about Being. Although we might all be
happy to say that everything is, โisโ itself does not seem to have any properties or attributes. Now for Heidegger this is an important clue, since it precisely shows us that Being and beings are not the same because we cannot use the same language to speak about them. In terms of the history of philosophy, however, the transcendence of Being merely proves it is โthe most universal and emptiest of concepts (BT: 2).
So, from Aristotleโs way of understanding Being, we end up with the idea it is indefinable, but this conclusion is only a result of us think- ing Being must be defined in exactly the same way as beings. Perhaps it is the classical form of definition which is inappropriate rather than that Being has no meaning, and is so unsuitable that some will even wind up saying the opposite. Not that Being is indefinable, but it is the most self-evident of concepts. Did not I just say that we use the meaning of Being in the most ordinary and everyday expression, such as โThe sky is blueโ and โI am happyโ, so why do we need to take it seriously as a philosophical problem?
Such sentences only demonstrate what the ordinary understanding of Being is. We cannot conclude from them that Being is meaning- less. Our difficulty just shows us there is a puzzle here, even in our everyday relation to the world. We already have an understanding of Being, since everyone knows what these ordinary sentences mean, and yet at the same time we cannot say precisely what this meaning is. Philosophy dismisses this ordinary understanding of Being, because philosophy rejects our everyday lives. To be a philosopher is to reject the ordinary world and the opinions of the โevery manโ. As we shall see, through our reading ofย Being and Time, this disapproval has to do with a particular bias in Western philosophy towards theoretical knowledge. It is just such a tendency which has led to the meaning of Being falling into perplexity. For Heidegger, therefore, it is exactly within our ordinary understanding of our relation to the world where we willย find the clues for reawakening the question of Being: โThe very fact that we already live in an understanding of Being and that the meaning of Being is still veiled in darkness proves that it is neces- sary in principle to raise this question againโ (BT: 23).
Before we can begin to ask this question, however, weย first must know what it is to ask a question at all. Perhaps we have a tendency, when asking questions, immediately to jump to the answer, and if we
cannotย find it, then we assume the question is not a serious one. What Heidegger wants us to do is to slow down (always important when you are doing philosophy). He wants us to ask ourselves what does it mean to ask a question, any question whatsoever, even if this question does not have an answer. This is important for two reasons. Generally, if we barge through questions without adequately thinking about what the question is asking us, then it is very likely we will come out with the wrong answer. Secondly, and more importantly, thinking about the question might actually give us a clue how we might go about ques- tioning itself. Rememberย Being and Timeย begins with a question. In fact, you could argue that the aim of this book is solely to reawaken this question (so that we might take it seriously again) and not to answer it (so if you think philosophy is about answers rather than questions, you might end up being disappointed).
Every question, Heidegger tells us, and not just the question of Being, can be broken down into three main elements:5
- What is asked about โย das Gefragtes
- What is interrogated โย das Befragtes
- What is discovered by asking this question โย das Erfragtes. (BT: 24)
How can we apply this list to Heideggerโs own question? What we are asking about is the meaning of Being, but in order to ask this ques- tion we need to interrogate a specific kind of being. Even though we already have a pre-understanding of Being, we cannot just ask directly about the meaning of Being, because, as we have already dis- covered, in reading theย first pages of the introduction, we end up having nothing to say at all. The only access to the meaning of Being is through beings. The further question, then, faces us: what being? As I sit at my table writing this chapter, I am surrounded by many kinds of beings: the light which shines on the papers I am reading, the pile of books I am using to try to understandย Being and Time, the pencil with which I am writing my notes, to name but a few. Can I pick one of these in order to begin my investigation? There is one important being, however, I have intentionally left out of my list, and that is myself, for I too am a being. We already know from the last sentences of our introduction that the kind of being I am has a certain impor- tance and significance for Heidegger. Before we get to why this is so,
let us ask about the other beings, and why they cannot be a route into the question of the meaning of Being.
Heideggerโs formal answer to why not is that his question has an โontological priorityโ (BT: 28). When I ask questions about the kind of beings I have given as examples, then what I am doing is asking what they are (in Heideggerโs vocabulary, he calls these ontical ques- tions, so as to distinguish them from ontological ones). The most sophisticated kind of questions in this fashion are scientific. If I really want to know what a pencil is, then I should ask a scientist, and not a philosopher. We live in a culture, perhaps, which tends to think the only important questions are scientific, but when it comes to the ques- tion of the meaning of Being, science has nothing to say. Negatively, we have already seen why this must be so, because if we take a scientific attitude (or a philosophical one which is largely inspired by it), then we cannot say anything about the meaning of Being at all. On its own, however, this does not really mean much, because this could just as equally be a proof that it is not really a proper question at all and we should just stay silent. Heidegger has to give us a posi- tive reason why we should carry on with this question.
Hisย first response is a very Husserlian (or even Kantian) one. All the sciences, no matter what they are, are โregional ontologiesโ (BT: 10). What he means by this is that they each, in their own turn, investigate a specific region or type of being. Thus, mathematics investigates mathematical objects; physics, physical ones; history, historical ones, and so on.6ย What none of these sciences studies is the meaning of Being as such, for if they did they would no longer be the disciplines they were, but something quite different, namely philosophy. This does not mean that the sciences do not have an ontology, but it is simply presupposed in order that scientists can get on with their work. The physicist, for example, does not worry about whether the uni- verse she is describing exists or not, but is merely concerned with whether her interpretation of the facts corresponds with what is taken to be true.7
I do not think, however, that the ontological priority of the ques- tion of the meaning of Being over the sciences is the most significant reason why Heidegger thinks we should treat this question seriously. There is a far more important reason and that is the ontic priority of the questioner (though as we shall see in a moment this ontic priority
is ontological). Let us remind ourselves about the structure of ques- tioning for Heidegger. When I ask about something, I must, so to speak, begin somewhere. The question is which being do I start with? The detour through the sciences is really to underline that I cannot just start with any being, because such investigations only presuppose an ontology but cannot, on their own terms, address it. There is one being, however, who asks the question in theย first place and that is myself. No doubt, I can be treated as though I were like any other being (this is what the sciences such as psychology and anthropology do, for example), but I am also very different from other beings, because I am the only being who is capable of asking what other beings are (the pencil does not ask what the light on my desk is). What Heidegger demonstrates is that such a gift, if that is what it is, is dependent upon the fact that my Being (not what I am, but the very fact that I am) can be an issue for me, which means that though I am a being, I am not just a being, and this is what Heidegger means when he writes, โDasein is ontically distinctive in that itย isย ontologicalโ (BT: 32. Emphasis in the original).
Existence
If I am a being, what am I? First of all, before we can answer this question, let us reflect upon Heideggerโs vocabulary, because he does not write โhuman beingโ, but โDaseinโ. Philosophers do not tend to invent new uses for words unless there is a very good reason to do so, and it is usually because they want us to look at our world in a different way. Words, like anything else, can become habits and thereby conceal more than they reveal. We all know what a human being is, and so to use the expression Dasein, which is usually left untranslated, is an attempt to break out of our preconceived ideas; and, as we already know from readingย Being and Time, it is all about liberating us from a dead ontology preventing us from experiencing our world as it appears rather than as we think it should. In German, Dasein can just mean existence, and more specifically human existence, but dic- tionary definitions tell us nothing about the philosophical meaning of a word. Heideggerโs use of the word โDaseinโ is much more specific than this. What it refers to is the ontological character of human exis- tence, which is entirely lacking in any other being, and which is why this being may be the only way into the question of Being as such.
What can I mean by the expression โontological characterโ? Again, when we use philosophical terms, it can make everything appear eso- teric and difficult, but what Heidegger is describing is an experience we all have, whether we are philosophers or not. My existence is a question for me.I worry about who I am, what I am doing, whether I am up to it at all. No doubt an animal can worry about where its next meal is coming from, but it does not worry about what it means to be an animal. My dog is not in anguish about what it is to be a dog; it just is. This is our tragedy, but it is also why we (unlike any other being) already have an understanding of Being, even if only in a confused way, because our Being is an issue for us and is always so. We are always caught up in the problem of our lives, even if we are running away from it. Science can give us no answers to these questions, because it can only tell me what I am, just as it can tell me what my dog is, but not how I am and why my existence as a whole matters to me. Even the scientist is a human being, and stands to his existence in the same way I do. Doing science is just one way of making sense of a life and giving it purpose, but โmaking sense of a lifeโ is not a scientific problem, but a human one.8
We tend to think of the word โexistenceโ applying to everything indiscriminately. We say the tree exists outside of my window, or the books on my table. But we also say ideas exist, like the idea of irra- tional numbers. We are even willing to entertain thatย fictional ideas exist (like unicorns), if only in our minds. For Heidegger, however, existence has a very precise and unique meaning inย Being and Time. It applies only to the kind of being we are. Not in terms of our reality, if we mean by reality that we exist like everything else in the universe. Rather we exist because we have an understanding of our Being as the very basis of our Being. The question of Being does not have its roots in a philosophical doctrine for Heidegger. It rises up from our everyday experience of ourselves and our world. Being matters to me as a question because my own Being is important to me. Of course, it is the task of philosophy to make this implicit understanding of Being, which Heidegger describes as โvagueโ and โaverageโ, explicit. But this does not mean it leaves this experience behind to ascend the lofty heights of theory and contemplation. Our everyday experience of ourselves is always the guide of the meaning of our existence for Heidegger and it is this meaning which allows us to free ourselves from mistaken interpretations of Being.
When I say my life matters to me, I do not mean life in general, but my life. Existence, for Heidegger, as we remarked at the end of the Introduction, is supremely individual. Only I can live my life. Even if I decide to live like others, then it is still I who has decided to do so. These choices I make in my life, which are mine even if I disavow them, Heidegger describes through the neologism โexistentiellโ. What is existentiell is an individual choice of someone, from as little as deciding to go to town in the afternoon, to becoming a physicist. The objective of theย first two divisions of Part one ofย Being and Timeย is to describe the underlying existential structure of the existentiell.9ย Again philosophy takes theย first investigation to be the most important, but without the existentiell, there would nothing to describe at all. The fact you are reading this book is an existentiell, that I wrote it in theย first place, and even that philosophy exists is because one day someone decided to be a philosopher. Just as I can only understand Being through beings, then I can only understand the existential, the particular Being of Dasein, through the existentiell. As Heidegger writes, โThe roots of the existential analytic, on its part, are ultimatelyย existentiellย (BT: 34, Heideggerโs emphasis).
The opposite to the existential understanding of Being is the cate- gorical. The categorical understanding of Being relates to those beings which I encounter in the world. It is this kind of Being which is taught in philosophy classes through those strange kind of questions like, โWhat is a chair?โ, โHow do I know the chair exists?โ or even, โHow do I know what I say about the chair is true?โ. All these are cat- egorical questions. Heidegger does not dismiss them, rather he argues they are utterly inadequate to investigating the existential meaning of Being. I am not a chair. I do not exist in the same way a chair does, but a chair only exists because I do. Yet there are those who speak about me as though I really were the same as a chair. When someone reduces the meaning of my existence to the difference between my genes and that of an ape or a banana, then no matter how sophisti- cated and scientifically true their conversation with me is, they are still reducing my Being to the Being of a thing. They will say I am more complex than a chair, but none the less I am just a thing like every other thing in the universe. I am made of matter and atoms like every- thing else or if they want to be more poetic, we are all made from the same dust of the stars.
Such a discourse is not false when it restricts itself to the narrow scientific perspective, but it is wrong to assume there is only categor- ical Being or to confuse existential Being with it. I could live my life through the human genome project, base all my choices on it, and interpret the whole of my existence through it, but then it would no longer be a scientific theory about observable facts. It would be exis- tential. Moreover, Heidegger would add, not only must we distinguish between the categorical and the existential, but the existential is more fundamental than the categorical. Chairs do not offer theories about the world. Science is a human activity. Like philosophy, it comes out of a particular way of Being in the world. Knowledge is a way we relate to things in attempting to comprehend them, but this relation is a particular way of existing in the world, and therefore the question of existence is more fundamental (ontologically speaking), than the problem of knowledge.
Two questions follow from this distinction between the existential and the categorical, and the priority of the former over the latter. First, why is it that I do interpret myself as a thing, and secondly, if I am not just a thing, what language can I use to describe who I am? In answer to theย first question, as with the question of the meaning of Being itself, we mustย find the source for this error in our everyday experience of the world. Basically, as part of our very Being-in-the- world, we become so absorbed and involved with things that we come to interpret ourselves as though we were just like these things too. This everyday absorption, which Heidegger calls โfallingโ (Verfallen), is further re-enforced by the philosophical tradition which offers us theories and hypotheses to support our self-misunderstanding, such that any other possible way of viewing our relation to ourselves and therefore to our world is almost impossible.10
One of Heideggerโs most important tasks is to allow us to free our- selves from this tradition which is preventing us from experiencing our Being as it really is, rather than what we think it ought to be. He calls this task โdestructionโ, but as we shall see it is not as negative as itย first might appear. It is not a matter of escaping our tradition completely, which Heidegger would think would be impossible anyway, but of seeing possibilities within it which it cannot see itself because of its own presuppositions and prejudices. What allows us, however, to see this bias invisible to it? Our guide is always the average everyday
understanding of Being which we all possess. We do not counter theory with another theory, but with experience. Yet here we encounter another problem, possibly the most difficult of all. How can we account for or describe this experience when the only language in which we can talk about the world is categorical? If we are going to capture the existential as existential, then we cannot use the proposi- tional language of predicates, attributes, concepts and categories. But it is precisely this language which we take to be the only true one.
How is Heidegger to surmount this problem? He will have to con- vince us there is a meaning of truth other than the categorical one. We have to wait until section thirty-three ofย Being and Timeย until weย find out what this truth might be, but before we get there, and as a summary of where we have got to so far, we can already say there are three ways in which Heidegger tries to avoid describing the existen- tial through the categorical, and they are all guided by the idea that it is our average everyday experience of the world which is the source for the meaning of Being. First of all, he uses ordinary language to describe our existence. Strangely enough, because we are so used to the technical language in philosophy, this sounds very obscure to our ears, and is one of the main reasons some have complained that Heidegger is too difficult. Secondly, as we saw from the introduction, he uses etymologies. Not so as to impress us with his knowledge of language, but to force us to rethink what our words mean in relation to our experience of ourselves and the world. Thus, if he reminds us of the etymology of the word โDaseinโ, then it is not because, like some lexicographer, he is interested in words for their own sake, but this etymology (literally โDaseinโ means โbeing thereโ) makes us think again about what it means to be human, in the way that the definition โrational animalโ does not because we have become too comfortable with it. Finally, and this is perhaps one of the most contentious aspects ofย Being and Time, he uses religious language. Not because the redis- covery of ontology requires belief, but the description of religious experience might be closer to what it is to be human, than a meta- physics ossified through constant use.11
The Destruction of Philosophy
History is not something that lies outside of us, as merely a series of facts and events, but it affects the very sense of ourselves in the
present. This explains why, even when I read, for example, an ancient text like Platoโsย The Symposium, it feels as though it were written yes- terday. This is not because Plato and the ancient Greeks thought just like me and that all human beings do so. On the contrary, the way that I think about myself and the world has come down to me from them. For the most part, my relation to my tradition is unconscious, so much so that what were once the most difficult and abstract theories about existence have become common sense. Dislodging this common sense is the most difficult of all tasks, because it is hard for us to see there is even a problem. It has taken thousands of years of inculcation to make us think that the meaning of Being is not a serious question. So one of theย first undertakings Heidegger has to perform is to show us that our common sense is not the result of our experience of the world, but is in fact the consequence of this tradition, which no longer affects us as a tradition at all but is just the way things are.
The source of our entrapment or bewitchment by the past belongs, as we have seen, in our relation to the world. In attempting to under- stand and control our external environment, we end up interpreting ourselves in the very same way as the things and objects we are involved with. In this way, the particular meaning of our existence is obscured andย finally lost. It is this everyday relation to the world which is re-enforced by philosophy. It takes this everyday misinterpretation of existence and gives it a metaphysical stamp of approval. Take, for example, the metaphysics of Plato. His explanation of the Forms can be seen as an analogy to the activity of a craftsman. In order to make a shoe, I already need in my mind, in advance, the idea of a shoe to produce it. We begin with an everyday activity in the world (making things or production) and this ordinary relation to things becomes the representation of Being as a whole and the meaning of human exis- tence. The whole universe, including myself, is the result of the cre- ative activity of theย demiurge.12ย This interpretation of Being as the Being of things is then subsequently repeated, with notable excep- tions, throughout the whole of the history of philosophy, so that now it appears to us as just common sense.
How, then, can we dislodge this tradition? First of all we must take it seriously; which is why throughout Heideggerโs career he constantly teaches and writes about the history of philosophy. This is not because he is interested in the history of philosophy for its own sake. He is not
a scholar in this sense (and this is perhaps why sometimes other schol- ars get so angry with him). He does not read Descartes simply to understand him on his own terms, but rather how Cartesian meta- physics has come to be handed down in such a way that even it is no longer seen as problematic. This requires a twofold method which Heidegger calls โdestructionโ (BT: 44).13ย This immediately sounds negative to our ears, as though we are supposed to turn our backs and forget about the past. This cannot be what Heidegger is suggesting, because the best way to ensure the past still has a hold upon us is by forgetting it. Theย first task of the destruction of the history of philos- ophy is to go back to the texts themselves and read them in detail to see how this metaphysical tradition has sustained and developed itself such that the question of the meaning of Being now appears totally irrelevant to us. From thisย first reading, however, necessarily follows the second, which is to show how these texts also always undermine and subvert themselves, and thereby indicate another way of think- ing about the meaning of Being, one that will sustain the writing ofย Being and Timeย itself.
Heidegger gives an indication of this more positive side of the destruction of the history of philosophy through his allusion to Kant (BT: 45). What we discover, in reading the texts of philosophy, is that every ontology is an interpretation of time. This is no more so than in Kantโs famousย Critique of Pure Reason. It is time which acts as the bridge between understanding and sensibility, which are the two sides of human knowledge of the world.14ย None the less, for all Kantโs proclamation in the preface and the introduction to his book that his thought marks a new beginning in the history of philosophy, for Heidegger, his ontology is merely a repetition of Descartesโ. Kantโs subject is still the subject of theย cogito, and not Dasein. Even Descartesโ ontology (despite his protestations) in theย Meditationsย and theย Discourse on the Methodย is a repetition of Scholastic thought, whose ontology has its basis in Aristotle.
The prejudice handed down over and over again through this tra- dition is that Being is always to be understood in terms of the present. As Heidegger writes, โEntities are grasped in their Being as โpres- enceโ; this means that they are understood with regard to a definite mode of time โ the โPresentย โ (BT: 47. Heideggerโs emphasis). Such an assumption places our involvement with things, and more specifically
our theoretical grasp of things, over and above our existence, which must be the basis of this relation. The question is whether our exis- tence can be understood through this priority given to the present. The whole aim of the second division ofย Being and Timeย is to show that the time of existence is not the same as the time of things. If the latter is the time of the present, then the former is the time of future, and if existence is to be the fundamental clue to the meaning of Being in general, then our ontology of time must also completely change.15
If we now go back to the structure of the question, we canย fill in its three elements. What is being asked about (Gefragtes), is the meaning of Being. What is interrogated (Befragtes), is the existence of Dasein. Andย finally, what is discovered (Erfragtes), is time as the horizon of ontology. Heideggerโs outline ofย Being and Timeย appears to follow the direction of this questioning (BT: 63โ4). Originally, it was designed to be in two parts. Theย first part consisted of three divisions: the analytic of Dasein; the interpretation of time in relation to this analytic, and following from this interpretation, the meaning of Being in general in terms of time. The second part was meant to consist of the des- truction of the history of philosophy from the perspective of the rediscovered temporal ontology, with one division each on Kant, Descartes and Aristotle. As anyone who has readย Being and Time, and as many commentators have pointed out, only theย first two divisions of part one were ever published. What we have in our hands, there- fore, is only a fragment. Does this mean we can see it as a failure even before we have begun reading it? Perhaps, but let us remind ourselves that philosophy is about questions and problems more than answers and solutions, and the very fact thatย Being and Timeย is incomplete might be more absorbing than if it were. What is really interesting is the missing third division of theย first part concerning time and Being. We canย find the three divisions of part two published afterย Being and Timeย (either in lectures or published works), and perhaps Heidegger felt that it would be ridiculous to insert them back into the new editions, but not โTime and Beingโ.16
Why is the last division of theย first part missing? The Being of Dasein was meant to be the guide to the meaning of Being in general, but Heidegger never takes this step. Perhaps because his own interpreta- tion of the relation between Dasein and the meaning of Being was too enmeshed in the tradition he was trying to escape. Does not
Heideggerโs argument, in a curious way, repeat the traditional tran- scendental arguments whichย find the source of the world in the subject? And does not such a transcendental argument subvert (or at least is in tension with) the overall historical and concrete approach ofย Being and Time? How can Dasein be both historical and transcendental?17
Being-in-the-World
When we think of the world in which we live, we might imagine it to be a space we occupy in the very same way a thing is inside a bigger thing. Am I not in the world, to use Heideggerโs example, as the water is inside the glass (BT: 79)? To think of our world in this way would be to confuse our way of Being with the Being of things, which is pre- cisely what we should not do. I do not exist in the same way as the glass does. There is no doubt that I can be treated that way. In a certain way of looking at things, I too can appear as a thing. Seen in a photograph, I might seem to a casual observer to be merely in a room in the same way that water is in a glass. Even here, though, it is possible to look at the picture in a different way. The expression of my face might tell you how I felt at the time. Perhaps I look miserable or uncomfortable. Perhaps my world was not quite right with me. The expression โmy worldโ, and the fact you understand it in a certain way, already tells you there is quite a difference between me and the water in the glass. In what sense can we say the water has its own world? Yet it is very easy for us to think about ourselves and others in this way. What else am I asking about when I meet you in the street and say, โHow are you?โ Am I not asking about your world?
We have already seen from the previous part that Heidegger makes a fundamental distinction between categorical and existential Being. Human beings are not just things. One way they are not things is that their Being is an issue for them. A chair does not ask what it means to be a chair, but you can ask what it means to be you. But if I exist, what do I exist in? Chapters two and three of theย first division ofย Being and Timeย are not only about interpreting this โinโ existentially and not cat- egorically, but also demonstrating that the categorical meaning of Being rises out of the existential (or in Heideggerโs language, the cat- egorical is โfoundedโ upon the existential). It is only because thingsย first matter to me (or the world is something that concerns me) that I
want to know about them, and not the other way around. This is the complete reversal of the philosophical tradition which takes knowing to be primary and our concern for the world to be secondary and merely subjective and personal.
In this part we will be looking at theย first three chapters of part one of theย first division ofย Being and Time, whose overall argument can be divided into two key questions: โWhat does it mean to exist?โ and โWhat does it mean to be in a world?โ Heidegger also offers a detailed deconstruction of Descartesโ account of nature (the only deconstruc- tion inย Being and Time, since Part two was never written) to show that it cannot make sense of how we live in the world, even though it is still the dominant scientific model of our age. Our own structure follows the articulation of Heideggerโs argument and has been divided into three sections: โMinenessโ, โWorldโ and โDescartes and Spatialityโ.
Mineness
The word โexistenceโ seems to be just as empty as the word โBeingโ. Does it not merely refer to the banal fact that there is something? Thus, I say the chair exists, the table, the computer and so on. Everything exists in an undifferentiated way. Even I exist in the same manner that all other things exist. But this is not what Heidegger means by existence. For mere existence, he uses the Latin wordย exis- tentiaย (BT: 67). But even this word has its origin in a dominant ontol- ogy of things that Heidegger wants to displace. Why should we think of the existence of things in this way? It is because a certain way of looking at things has been handed down to us from the past which we do not even think about any more, which is what it means to be is simply to be present in a uniform manner. Such a way of being, Heidegger calls โpresent-to-handโ (Vorhandensein). But why should this be the only way in which things exist, and more importantly is this the way that I exist? Could there be a way of existing that is different, and specifically is Dasein such a different way of existing?
One way that Heidegger (in section nine [BT: 67โ71]) distinguishes our way of existing from things is that I can talk about my existence as being mine. This goes back to what he already said in the intro- duction toย Being and Timeย that the ontic priority (remembering that โonticโ means that we are speaking about a specific being) of Dasein is that its Being is an issue for it (a dog does not worry about Being a
dog; it just is one). Heidegger is not denying that my Being could not be of concern for others, but fundamentally if it were not so for me, then it would not be for others either. โMy beingโ(one possible trans- lation forย Jemeinigkeit, rather than mineness, as long as we understand Being here as a verb and not a noun โ a way of Being and not a sub- stantive) is the condition for the kind of care others have for me.18
How then are we to think about existence as something that could be mine? It is not a property we have, as when we say red is a prop- erty of a red thing. To think of existence as mine is to understand it in terms of possibilities. Stones do not have possibilities. The stone does not choose to be a stone. Animals do not have possibilities. My dog cannot wake up one day and decide not to be the dog it is. It acts through instinctual behaviour. I, however, can decide to be a student of philosophy, a doctor or a teacher or many other things. Of course my possibilities are not endless. I am aย finite being, not an infinite one. An Aztec warrior could not have decided to become an astronaut, and if I am serious, I cannot really become an Aztec warrior (that is really be one). None the less, I still have to take a stand upon my exis- tence, even if one way of doing so is to drift about in boredom and indecision.19
It is because Daseinโs existence is understood in terms of possibili- ties and not properties, that every existence is singular. Everyoneโs existence is an issue for them individually. Of course, it is perfectly possible that we might face the same possibilities (and this is more than likely to be so since we share the same world), but how we face our possibilities and what they might mean to us is always going to be deeply personal. Later, in our reading ofย Being and Time, we willย find that there is one possibility which we do all share, which is the possibility of our impossibility, which is our death.20ย What matters to Heidegger, however, is not the objective fact of our deaths (common to all life and not just human beings), but how each one of us, faces or does not face this possibility, since no one else can die our death. In other words, our Being towards this possibility is in every case our own.
But how can possibility be the distinguishing mark of Daseinโs exis- tence? Do I not also speak of things in the language of possibility? Think of the philosophersโ famous example of the acorn and the oak tree. Do they not speak of the oak tree being the possibility of the
acorn? Why is this any different from my possibilities? Precisely because we cannot talk of the acornโs possibility being its own. It is the same possibility for acorn A as it is for acorn B, and we cannot say that the one acorn lives its possibility differently from the other. It is true that in the course of time the development of one possibility might differ from the other. One acorn might have fallen on stony ground and never germinated, but this difference has to do only with external circumstances which belong indifferently to its existence and not with a relation of the acorn to its own possibility (and this is the case even if we think of something being wrong with the seed itself. It is not something it decides or chooses).
It is because the acorn exists indifferently towards its possibilities that it can be investigated scientifically. Human beings, as Heidegger points out in the following section, can also be objects of scientific study as in anthropology, psychology and biology, but then they are treated as though they were just complicated things, no different from any thing else which exists (BT: 71โ5). It is precisely this way of looking at the world that Heidegger wants us to question. Why should we take this ontology to be the only true one? Moreover, the scientific viewpoint does not even take its own ontology seriously. It takes for granted that things exist and that we can speak about existence in the same way about everything, but it does not presume that this ontol- ogy is worthy of serious study.21ย What is lost in this ontology is the way of Being of human beings. I am like an acorn in that if do not eat or have water I will die, but I am not like an acorn, in that I can be a student, a teacher or even a reader ofย Being and Time. Even in relation to theย first possibilities, if I think about it, I am not really like an acorn. For I have to ask myself why do I bother eating and drinking? What is it all for? What is the purpose and point of my life? This existentialย telosย has nothing at all to do with nature (in fact nature has no purpose). It can only have a meaning in relation to an existence which can be called mine.
Of course, you might be thinking about the meaning of your life whilst you are reading this, but for the most part, if we are serious, we do not. In fact, for the most part we live like acorns (or perhaps like animals). We have no attitude to our possibilities at all. We just live them out of habit and ritual (I could tell you what I do every morning, and it does not change). Here Heidegger introduces one of the most
important distinctions ofย Being and Time, between authenticity and inauthenticity (BT: 68). Again this is one of the places where knowing the German is useful. The word that is translated as โauthenticโ isย eigentlich, which derives from the adjectiveย eigen, meaning โownโ. I can either own or disown my existence. I can choose to be who I am or just live my life without choosing at all. This is the real ontological difference between me and the acorn. It cannot choose to be its pos- sibilities. It just is them, or they fail to happen. And this is the same for my dog. It just is its possibilities, or not. It might not wish to go for a walk in the pouring rain, but it cannot decide it does not want to live this life any more in its totality. I might suddenly despair being a student or a teacher, or any other human possibility, because I realise that I never made a decision to be this anyway, but just went ahead because everyone else did it.
Having made this distinction between authentic and inauthentic existence, we might think that Heidegger would use authentic exis- tence as the template for what it is to be a human being, but he does not. On the contrary, he begins with average everyday existence (BT: 69). Authentic existence is something you or I choose in relation to our possibilities. I cannot begin with a specific possibility and then use it to define what it is to be a human being (let us say being a philoso- pher), for that would be to treat possibilities as properties which could be defined in advance, as when I define the perfect acorn as one that has a certain size, shape and colour in relation to which all other acorns are to be measured. Again, existence for Heidegger means โways of Beingโ. โWays of Beingโ, so to speak, are personal (they are in each case something that we own or do not own). They are not a list of objective properties which we mightย find in a encyclopaedia or text book.
It is precisely this existence, the average and the everyday, which
the philosophical tradition has passed over. Indeed, it has seen as its ultimate purpose and goal to get as far away from the everyday as pos- sible. Plato would have said that the everyday belongs merely to โopinionโ (doxa). Today we might think of it as โsubjectiveโ, which has nothing at all to do with the truth of things. What we want to know is the objective world of facts and principles, and not the everyday worries and anxieties of people (and even if we are interested in these, then we want to know about them objectively). This is to think of our
existence as a derivative of the Being of things, and not, as Heidegger wants to show us in the two chapters that follow, the Being of things as descended from ours. Things only have a meaning because we already exist in a world, and this world belongs to our everyday exis- tence, even though philosophy, and the science that comes from it, continually confuses the world with a thing when they interpret it as nature.
World
As we have already remarked, we can speak about Being in two ways for Heidegger, either categorically and existentially.22ย Theย first belongs to things and the second to the Being of Dasein. Western phi- losophy (since Aristotle) has continually confused the latter with the former. One way of thinking of the difference between these two ways of Being is through the simple proposition โinโ. When we say we exist in a world what do we mean by the word โinโ? Is not inhabiting a world like one thing being inside another thing, but on a bigger scale? We remember the childhood cartoon of a boy who is sitting on a boat in a lake, and then the view keeps moving further back from the town, to the country, to the world, andย finally to the universe, as though existing were the same as being inside one thing after the other until we come to the largest thing which is the universe (we even wonder what might be outside of the universe). However moving and wondrous this picture might be, it is entirely inappropriate to the Being of Dasein. It confuses our way of Being with the Being of things. It is the water in the glass which exists in this Russian doll uni- verse, not us. Of course, viewed from a scientific way of looking at things, we can be seen in this way, but it is Heideggerโs argument that this is not fundamental to our way of Being. We exist as a โwhoโ and not as a โwhatโ (BT: 71).
It is very hard to stop thinking about ourselves as things, but Heidegger uses another example of a chair to help us (BT: 81). Our relation to our world is not like the relation to a thing in space. The world is something in which we exist, but โinโ here does not mean being inside something, but โbeing alongsideโ.23ย Heidegger interprets โbeing alongsideโ in the more primary sense of familiarity. I am in the world as being at home. The world is where I live, and living in the world is quite different from water being in a glass. One way in which
my world is familiar to me is that I encounter things within it which are part of my everyday experience. The cup, the kettle and the teapot, for example, which are part of my morning ritual; without which, I commonly say to others, I would not be able to function. I encounter these things in my world, but one thing we can say about things is that they do not encounter other things. We can say the chair is touching the wall which it is leaning against, but there really is not an encounter between them, but only a spatial relation of contiguity.
How then do we relate to the world, if we do not do so as a thing is next to another thing? Again we have to go back to our everyday experience to provide the clue. This is to reverse the whole trajectory of the history of philosophy, which tends to understand the question of the existence of the world as one of knowledge. It imagines that I am a worldless being which somehow has to get outside of itself in order toย find the world. For Heidegger, on the contrary, I am already in the world, and the problem of the existence of the external world begins only if you understand the Being of Dasein as the same as the Being of things. This is the primary way, as we saw in the introduc- tion, that Heidegger differs from his teacher Husserl. For the latter takes epistemology, which is the problem of knowledge of the exter- nal world, as being the basic question of philosophy. Heidegger would say to Husserl that Daseinย first of all has to exist before it can know anything. In the language of section thirteen ofย Being and Timeย (which ironically in this case is taken from Husserl), knowing is a โfoundedโ mode of existence (BT: 86).
In this way of thinking about the world (which has its origin in Descartes), the relation between the world and Dasein is thought through the difference between a subject and an object. In epistemol- ogy, the world is understood as external nature which in some strange and peculiar sense is โout thereโ. The single most important problem of epistemology is how do we get from the inner sphere of the subject to the outer sphere of nature, since both are entirely different kinds of being. Although epistemology does think of the subject and the object as being different, it leaves this difference totally obscure.ย Being and Timeย throws light on this darkness by asking the question directly, โWhat does it mean to be the kind of being that I am?โ
As long as I am not seduced by metaphysics, I can see I exist along- side the world as something which is familiar to me. The world is not
an alien object where I somehow have to wonder about how I got there and how I relate to it. I am my world as that which is intimate to me, to the extent that the world, in my everyday existence, is not a problem for me at all. This relation to the world can only be under- stood, Heidegger argues, through an ontology of care, which is more primordial than the abstract knowledge of things. Thingsย first of all matter to me in a world I care about.24ย Only in a second moment, do I have a relation to them in terms of knowing. Knowledge, rather than being the essential relation to things, as metaphysics interprets it, is secondary. To know something is to hold ourselves back from our normal involvement in the world. This is why philosophical examples sound so peculiar and alien, as when a teacher addresses a student and points to a chair and says โWhat is it?โ We do not really relate to chairs in this way when we go about our world, and it is only because the philosopher speaks about things in this odd way that the world suddenly becomes a problem for us.
In the example of perception as our model of the relation to the world, the context of my experience is stripped away. We are left with the empty existential correlation of the eye with a thing (where the eye itself is just seen as another thing): this chair, this table, this room and so on until again we end up with the universe. But my primary relation to things is that they matter to me. The table is for putting something on, the chair for sitting and the room for listening to lec- tures. The epistemological problem of the world is a false one. It is not that Heidegger (in section thirteen) proves that the world exists in a better way than Descartes, Kant or Husserl, rather he shows that the question is nonsensical as soon as we realise that the Being of Dasein is not the same as the Being of a thing (BT: 86โ90). We do not have to get from an โinsideโ to an โoutsideโ to understand our relation to the world, because we are already outside of ourselves in our involvement with things which matter to us.
We need to think in a deeper way, then, exactly what we mean by the expression โworldโ and this is how Heidegger begins chapter three, โThe Worldhood of the Worldโ. I know that I relate to things outside of me (houses, trees, people, mountains, stars, Heidegger writes), but is the world just a collection of these things (BT: 91)? By simply making a list of things, the meaning of the world is in fact concealed from us because we end up thinking of it as a thing. We conceive of
the world as a container in which things like houses, trees, people, mountains and stars simply exist, and we end up calling this container โnatureโ or โthe universeโ. Rather than understanding the world through the nature, we need to understand nature through the world, but we can only do so if we equally understand the world existentially and not categorically. This would mean that rather than the world being a category of things (the physical space in which they are found) it is an existential way of Being of Dasein. It is because Dasein has a world, or having a world belongs essentially to its way of Being, that things like houses, trees, mountains and stars also have a world (one way of which is Being in nature).
Heidegger tells us in section fourteen that there are four ways of speaking about the world (BT: 93):
- As an ontical concept which expresses the totality of beings. What is meant by the words โnatureโ or โcosmosโ.
- Ontologically, as the way of Being of these beings which are defined above.
- Ontically again, but as the world of a particular Dasein.
- Finally ontologically, as what it means for any Dasein to belong to a world. What Heidegger calls โworldhoodโ (Weltlichkeit).
The meaning of the world that concerns Heidegger inย Being and Timeย is the last one: the ontological significance of the world which belongs to Dasein. A world, (the world that you or I live in) is cultural and his- torical, specific to a people and can live and die. What we are inter- ested in, however, is the general meaning of the world, which is true of every world, whether we are thinking about our world today or the world of the Aztecs in the sixteenth century. But how are we to get to this world which is at the bottom of every world? The answer to this question again is our everyday experience, for only in this way can we break through the assumptions which prevent us from understanding the world correctly. The world that is closest to us Heidegger calls the โenvironmentโ, which in German isย Umwelt, the world which sur- rounds us.
To โseeโ this everyday world, we must describe how things we encounter really present themselves in our dealings with them, andย fight against our temptation to over-interpret them, for example,
in the models of perception. We must follow, in other words, what Heidegger has already described as the phenomenological method: interpret what you see as it shows itself in itself.25ย We relate to thingsย first of all because they matter to us and not because we need to know what they are in the abstract way in which philosophy describes them. For this reason, weย first of all encounter things, Heidegger tells us in sectionย fifteen, not as objects of knowledge but as โtoolsโ or โequip- mentโ (Zeug) which are useful for us (BT: 97). Moreover, we never just encounter one piece of equipment in isolation, like the chair or table which the philosopher points to in her lectures. Rather, one item of equipment always refers to another one. I open the door in order to leave the room. I walk down the corridor in order to leave the build- ing. I leave the building in order to buy a cup of coffee and so on. Thus, unlike in perception, I do not see a thing as separate from every- thing else, rather things are tools which always relate to other things. This experience of the interrelation between equipment (what Heidegger calls their โassignmentโ or โreferenceโ) should not be con- fused with a mere collection of things (as when we thought of the world as container in which things like houses, trees, people, moun- tains and stars simply exist). Rather, I am at home with them. I do not enter a room and start counting things and measuring the distance between them. I do not experience the roomย first of all as a geomet- rical but as a living space where things relate to each other in terms of my everyday dealings with them.
I go into my living room. I switch on the television with my remote
control and sit down on my sofa and watch (absent-mindedly, perhaps) the programme. All these things are present to you now reading this (you might even be imagining your own living room), but when you think of it in the actual action itself are these things ever present? They are present now in my recollection of it, but ordinar- ily I do not notice the television or the remote control or the sofa. Things disappear in their use. I do not have a theory of my living room. I just make use of it. It is not looking at the hammer, Heidegger tells us, which reveals the being of the hammer as a tool, but hammering (BT: 98).
We must sharply distinguish, therefore, between what is present as an object of knowledge (what Heidegger callsย Vorhandenseinย โ present- to-hand) from what reveals itself or does not reveal itself in use
(Zuhandenseinย โ ready-to-hand). No matter how hard I look at the hammer, I can never disclose its โready-to-handnessโ. As soon as something is called to my attention, then it becomes present-to-hand. The hammer ceases to be a โhammering nails into the wood in order to build a houseโ, but is simply a hammer with certain properties. What concerns me when I use something is not the thing itself, but the purpose which it fulfils. I am watching television because I am tired or even to avoid the work I am supposed to be doing.
The whole drive of Heideggerโs analysis in sectionsย fifteen and sixteen is to show that my everyday involvement with things already involves and implies a world. My relation to things takes place in my activity which only makes sense through my existence and which in turn only has a meaning within a world. All of this he calls the โtowards whichโ of equipment which makes up its network of refer- ences or assignments (BT: 99). The reason why the phenomenon of the world is so difficult to see, and why we can understand that it is so easy to confuse it with nature, is that it is invisible in two ways:ย firstly, in the scientific and philosophical model of perception where things are ripped out of their context and simply looked at; and secondly, in my everyday involvement with things where, because I am so occu- pied, the world disappears into the background. As I slump in front of my television, it is highly unlikely that I will notice my world.26ย It only becomes visible when it is interrupted.27
We can imagine Heideggerโs phenomenology as a making explicit of what occurs in these breaks. Every night I walk into my room and switch on the television at a certain time. One day I do the same and the television does not work. Suddenly, in that moment, the meaning of my world reveals itself. What is made visible is the interrelation between things. My world is not one of them, but the relation between them โ the significance of my world. This significance, which is more like aย flavour than a concept, is neither present, nor ready-to- hand. On the contrary, it refers back to my existence.
The world as the interrelationship of things is further reinforced in section seventeen through the analysis of signs (BT: 107โ83). Signs are important for Heidegger not because they are not just symbols or indicate something, but because they reveal the world in which we live. In one sense, all equipment is a sign, because every piece of equipment refers to another piece of equipment whose interlocking
is given a significance through a world which for the most part is invis- ible to those who participate in it, because it is simply part of โgetting aroundโ. Heideggerโs example is the indicator of car (which at the time he was writing would have been a small red arrow) (BT: 108โ9). The position of the red arrow determines the direction in which the car will move at a crossroads and is controlled by the driver. In this way, the indicator is a tool which has a use within the general context of driving, not only for the driver but for other drivers as well. We might say the red arrow indicates I am turning left or right. This indi- cation, however, Heidegger asserts, is not primary. To make sense of this indication I have to refer to a deeper ontological structure which he calls โserviceabilityโ (Dienlichkeit) (BT: 109).
Signs indicate because theyย first of all provide a service. They do not provide a service because they indicate. What then is the source of the service signs provide? It is ourselves. If we did not need to indi- cate turning to the left or the right (or we did not live in a world in which such an action made sense), then there would be no indicators. Or look at it this way: there would be no indicators on cars if there were not intersections; there would be no intersections if there were not roads; but there would be no roads if human beings did not make journeys. And why do we make journeys? Here we are beginning to ask the important ontological question about the world. We make journeys because we have projects. I might be running away from something, or I could just be going to work or delivering the post. We might even imagine an existential journey, a great line ofย flight which is so common to much American literature andย film. In each case, whether consciously or not, every journey expresses the way in which someone takes a stand or interprets his existence. It is a way to be.
Signs reveal the world in which I live which is the basis of equip- mentality. This world is not nature, if we imagine by this word the mathematical representation of geometrical space. Theย first part of section eighteen acts as a summary of all that we have so far hope- fully understood (BT: 114โ22). My everyday involvement with things already involves a world, even though this might not be explicit to me. This world is not a thing (it is neither present or ready-to-hand) but is the context in which my use of things makes sense, what Heidegger calls its โtowards whichโ and โfor whichโ (BT: 114). Such purposes are not properties of things, rather they refer back to the being of Dasein,
whose possibilities link things together. To use Heideggerโs example, I would not be hammering this nail into this piece of wood, if I were not making this hut in order to secure myself against the vagaries of the weather (BT: 116). The fundamental โtowards whichโ, therefore, is the โin order toโ of Dasein.
Any particular involvement with a thing only makes sense within a totality of involvements. The question โWhy am I building this hut?โ can only be answered through what my world means to me, but this world is not something that stands outside of me like a thing. Indeed, it is not a โsomethingโ at all. Rather it is the basic familiarity that I have with things. Such an involvement is not a theoretical reasoning, in which things appear in front of me like snapshots, but the way in which I am comfortable with my surroundings. Being-in-the-world, therefore, is not a property which Dasein could choose or not choose to have. It belongs ontologically to what Dasein is. Without this world which every Dasein, so to speak, carries along with itself in its involve- ment with things, things themselves would neither be present nor ready-to-hand. My world illuminates or gives significance to things (in Heideggerโs language, it โfreesโ them to be what they are).
The metaphysical tradition, and the scientific world view that is sustained by it, even if unconsciously, takes the world, on the contrary, to be a physical thing of which Dasein is just one thing amongst others. We have to understand this perspective, and more importantly its ontological deficiencies, because it blocks our own understanding of what the world really is. Heideggerโs example of such a mistaken view is Descartes.
Descartes and Spatiality
We remember that for Heidegger it is not possible to get back to our experience of the world without โdestroyingโ the tradition which clouds our own understanding. The history of philosophy is not just the dusty shelves of books in a library, but affects the way all of us think. This is why the second part in the plan ofย Being and Timeย was meant to be a destruction or deconstruction of three of the most important thinkers of this tradition: Kant, Descartes and Aristotle. We know that Heidegger never completed this part, but most of it was achieved in other publications. None the less in this section ofย Being and Timeย (โA contrast between our analysis of worldhood and
Descartesโ Interpretationโ [BT: 122โ34]), Heidegger gives a clear indication of what his treatment of Descartes would have been if he had written the second part.
We might also ask ourselves the question, why Descartes and not some other philosopher? The answer to this question is twofold:ย first, Descartes is important because he is the mainstay or foundation of our scientific conception of the world as nature; and second, (perhaps more importantly), his has become the common sense interpretation of the world, even amongst those who have not read a word of phi- losophy or have even heard the name Descartes. Such a view of the world is just taken to be true, even though it runs counter to our own experience of ourselves. The aim of Heideggerโs destruction is to show how Descartesโ description of nature is ontologically inade- quate in understanding our world, but also to show the superiority of own existential analysis in this task. It ends, therefore, with the existential explanation of space, which we can contrast with the geometrical one.
What is at fault in the Cartesian interpretation of the world is a confusion of ontological difference. It translates an ontic definition of things into an ontological explanation of the world. In other words, it takes a scientific description of things to be equivalent to our expe- rience of the world, but as we have seen the world is not a thing, whether ready or present-to-hand, but the way of Being of Dasein. How then does Descartes understand the nature of things? He com- prehends them through the metaphysical concept of extension, which is essentially spatial. The fundamental distinction, Heidegger asserts, in Descartesโ philosophy is between nature and spirit (BT: 123). The difference between them is internal to the idea of substance. Nature is material and spirit immaterial. The essential attribute of nature is extension, which is the real being of the world. All that exists is a mode of extension, including shape and motion and all other prop- erties of matter. What is at the heart of this metaphysical conception of the world is the notion of Being as permanence, but as Heidegger has already pointed out to us, this is not something new at all but has its source in Parmenidesโ interpretation of Being as โthat simple awareness of something present-to-hand in its sheer present-to-handโ (BT: 48). Ontologically speaking, Descartes is not revolutionary at all, even though he presents himself as so being, but is merely the
continuation of a long metaphysical tradition which began with the ancient Greeks.
It is we who are reading Descartes, after going through the analytic of Dasein, who are aware of his ontological presuppositions. He, on his part, is completely ignorant of them, and like those to whom the opening pages ofย Being and Timeย are addressed, no longer takes Being as a serious philosophical question, because it is defined as substance which is said to be inaccessible. It is marked by a theological silence. The world is interpreted as extension, but the ontology of substance is left unclear. This substance itself is interpreted ontically, such that the difference between the ontological and the ontic is also left unclear, but it is precisely this difference which is the key question and problem.
What we have to understand is that Descartesโ ontology is not an ontology of the world at all, since extension can only be thought through a thing. The world is just one type of thing amongst other things. We have to ask ourselves how Descartes has ended up with such a distorted picture of the world. It is because he takes the scientific understanding of things as the only possible relation to the world. What is at the heart of this mathematical physics is the ontol- ogy of the present-to-hand, where the world, as the way of being of Dasein, is completely invisible. What matters to him is only how we know things, and not Being. His assumptions predetermine his description of the appearance of phenomenon, rather than letting them appear as they show themselves. Everything is reduced to a mathematicalย figure. This is not to deny the truth of mathematics, but it is to accuse Descartes of confusing a regional with a general ontol- ogy. The language of mathematics tells us something about mathe- matical objects but not about the meaning of Being in general.
Not only does Descartesโ explanation leave us completely in the dark about what the world is, it also obscures the Being of Dasein. For it too is interpreted through the metaphysical category of substance. True, it is conceived through thought and not extension, but such a way of thinking about Dasein makes it absolutely impossible to understand our practical involvement with things in the world which is the everyday basis of our existence. The philosopher comes up with a picture of the world which has nothing at all to do with how we live, and then we are supposed to drop our profound sense of ourselves for
their narrow truth. Descartes compresses the meaning of the world to the ontology of things which are present-to-hand whose only access is through mathematical formulas; but what does this have to do with how we really experience the world? Am I computing math- ematical equations when I reach out for a glass in order to drink some water? Am I calculating a series of zeros and ones, when I say to someone that I love them? When we think about it, what a peculiar view of human beings this is, even though we take mathematics, and the science which is based upon it, to be the only true interpretation of the world.28
That Descartes passes over the phenomenon of the world is not an error on his part, but belongs essentially to the way that Dasein relates to the world. We become so involved with things that we begin to interpret ourselves as though we were just like them. It is also a way ofย fleeing from our Being and our responsibility for ourselves. Such an experience of our Being also becomes justified by the philosophi- cal tradition, which takes this inauthentic way of being and sets it into stone as the true picture of the world. Any ontical science (however interesting and true it might be on its own terms) cannot be an answer to an ontological question. We have seen that the world is grounded in the way Dasein exists, and not in some mysterious properties of things which are taken as a fact. For even science, and the way that it investigates things, mustย first of all come from the way Dasein exists. After all, scientists themselves are human beings.
How then does Dasein exist in space, if it does not do so as a thing? This question is answered by the last part of chapter three, โThe Aroundness of the Environment, and Daseinโs Spatialityโ (BT: 134โ 48). Hopefully, we already recognise now that if we are going to understand Daseinโs spatiality, then we have to do so through our practical involvement with things and not through a supposedly โobjectiveโ knowledge of them. It is phenomenologically incorrect to suggest that things which are ready-to-hand are related to us through the abstract space of geometry. Things are near and far to the extent we are involved and interested in them and not because of the math- ematical distance between us. Existentially speaking, the laptop into which I am typing these words is closer to me than the glasses that are on the end of my nose which I never notice, even though in terms of measured distance the glasses are closer to me than the laptop
(Heideggerโs example is spectacles and a picture of the wall [BT: 141]).
Such practical places are not an objective property of things or of the world understood as nature, but belong to the existence of Dasein. It is I who give places to things, not things that place me, and things only have their places or โregionsโ, as Heidegger calls it, because they matter to me (BT: 136). Something is near or faraway from me, not because of an objectively measured distance, but because of my concern for it. Moreover, the objective distance between things would only be significant for me if I was already involved in them. The objec- tive distance between the Earth and the Sun is only significant and intelligible because understanding the solar system is something of great interest to us. This is not to reduce the objective distance between things to a mere subjective phenomenon. There really is 150,000,000 kilometres between the Earth and the Sun, but such a fact is ontical and not ontological. What we have to ask ourselves is why such a fact interests us and if this is the only way to relate to the Sun.29
Daseinโs primary interest in things Heidegger calls โde-severanceโ and โdirectionalityโ (BT: 138). De-severance is the English translation of the German wordย Ent-fernung. Heidegger uses the hyphen to emphasise the idea that in taking interest in things Dasein removes the distance between it and them. It does so because of its own projects and possibilities. Equally, things have a direction only in relation to me, whether we take direction in a limited sense as being left and right or in the more fundamental sense of the โin order toโ. It belongs to Daseinโs way of being that it brings, both practically and theoretically, things close to itself. In one sense, this expresses the familiarity and intimacy of our world, where everything has its place, but as modern technology, it can also lead to the destruction of the mystery of things, where paradoxically the removal of distance only has the conse- quence of defamiliarisation:
In Dasein there lies an essential tendency towards closeness. All the ways in which we speed things up, as we are more or less compelled to do today, push us on towards the conquest of remoteness. With the โradioโ, for example, Dasein has so expanded its everyday environment that it has accomplished a de- severance of the โworldโ โ a de-severance which, in its meaning for Dasein, cannot yet be visualised. (BT: 140. Heideggerโs emphasis)30
In summary, the world is always there in some way for us. We are not โworldlessโ beings, as philosophy sees us, which somehow have toย find our way back into a world. We already live in a world. We are already outside of ourselves in a world. This world is not the world of knowledge and cognition, but of practical involvement and concern. Indeed, it is this world which is the condition for knowledge. If our world were not something which mattered to us, then we would not investigate and inquire into things. But the world is not a thing, and we are not things which are inside a larger thing. The world is the way of Being of Dasein. Its only meaning is Daseinโs understanding of itself. It is a web of meaning through which we discover our orienta- tion and direction. Such a web, as Dreyfus constantly reminds us, cannot be an object of knowledge, because it is not something we have to know or believe in.31ย On the contrary, to have a belief or to know something requires that this web already exists. The world is the background significance of all our everyday practices from which everything that is of concern and interest to us springs, including philosophy.
Others, Language and Truth
Heidegger already speaks of others when he describes the Being of equipment and the relation to the world which is visible there. So as not to clutter up my own analysis with too much material, I did not directly refer to them. How then are others already there when I am working with or using things? They are present in the fundamental โin order toโ of Daseinโs Being. In relating to things as ready-to-hand, I already related to those others which Heidegger says belong to the โpublic worldโ (BT: 100). Just as much as the problem of the existence of the world is a headache which has been induced by too much phi- losophy, so too is the existence of other minds.32ย The origin of this view has its source in the same metaphysics which sees the world as having a thing like nature. As we have seen, we cannot understand Daseinโs Being through such a conception as though it were merely a thing. Just as much as I am not in the world like water in a glass, then others are not separate from me. My relation to others already belongs to the way that I am, and I cannot understand my own Being apart from them. I am with them from the very beginning.
If in this chapter we shall look more specifically at how Heidegger describes our relation to others in our everyday world, we shall also examine his deepening of analysis of how Dasein is in the world. The difference between chapterย five, โBeing-In as Suchโ, and chapter three, โThe Worldhood of the Worldโ, is that โbeing-inโ is now described primarily through moods, language and understanding and not our practical relation to things in the world. If Daseinโs Being is characterised as โBeing-in the-worldโ, then so far we have only inves- tigated the world. Our next task, therefore, is to analyse the โBeing-inโ of Dasein, how and in what way we live in a world. In the previous chapter, this was for the most part described negatively. Dasein does not live in the world in the way that a thing occupies space. Now, our question is positive: what is the determinate way in which Dasein is in a world? Increasingly, the object of fundamental ontology becomes the particular way of Being of Dasein (what makes us different from any other beings), until it culminates in the famous description of โBeing-towards-deathโ in the opening pages of the second division.
This part is divided into three sections: โThe Theyโ, โMoods, Understanding and Languageโ andย finally โTruthโ. Hitherto our order of explanation (apart from our jumping ahead to phenomenology in the introduction) has followed the order ofย Being and Time. Now, since itย fits better with the topics themselves, we are going to leap forward to the interpretation of truth in section forty-four. This is without doubt one of the most important sections inย Being and Time. Heidegger returns again and again to this theme in his later writings, and it is the key to comprehending his notion of Being.33ย I shall leave my discus- sion of โfallingโ until the beginning of the next part.
The They
Just as with the distinction between the authentic and the inauthen- tic, we should not take the difference between myself and others as being a moral or social one. Heidegger is not bemoaning the fact that none of us today is really an individual (of course, as everyone knows, those who shout loudest that they are individuals are always the ones who are least so), but is describing the way of Being of Dasein. It belongs essentially to Daseinโs Being that it is already with others in the world. It is for this reason that we have already come across the phenomenon of others in the description of the world as our
environment in which we pursue our daily tasks. It does not matter whether I am with others or not in the factual sense, for whatever I do already indicates the presence of others, even if they are absent. In writing this book now, I am already in relation to the others who will read it, though of course it would be profoundly uncomfortable if these others were actually in my room as I write. If Heidegger does make a social comment, so for example when he remarks that in our everyday existence we tend to โread, see and judge about literature and art asย theyย see and judgeโ (BT: 164. Heideggerโs emphasis), he does not mean by this that it is a modern curse which we have somehow to throw off, but that understanding ourselves in this way is part of our everyday existence. The ontological analysis must comeย first, other- wiseย Being and Timeย would just be sociological treatise in a very limited sense, as merely an interesting list of opinions about the modern world which we might suspect are only the opinions of the researcher. No doubt from the ontological analysis we might make social com- ments (and Heidegger certainly does), but such statements do not invalidate the ontology.
What then is at issue in Heideggerโs analysis of the โTheyโ (or the โAnyoneโ as some others translate the German,ย Das Man)? It is the answer to the question, who is Dasein. Now we might have thought we had already answered this question, when Heidegger wrote at the beginning of division one that Dasein is in each case โmineโ (BT: 68). We remember that what distinguishes existence from the mere exist- ing of a thing is that my existence is something I have to accomplish. Rather than just being given, it is a drama or task. So why do we have to talk about the They? Precisely because existence is a drama and not just a definition of something. I have to struggle to make my existence mine. It is a possibility I can have or lose. It is not an actuality which belongs to a thing as part of its definition (as a triangle has three sides). If I have to make my existence mine, then there must be something against which I have toย fight, and this is the meaning of the They.
Again we have to be very careful not to read this as a moral lack on
my part, as though Heidegger were making a statement that it is ter- rible that so many people do not live individual lives any more (which must be one of the most inauthentic statements ever uttered). Daseinโs involvement and absorption in the world, as we have already seen, is not a failure on its part, but is the very way in which we exist in the
world. Such everyday existence is anonymous, and it is from this back- ground that I have to wrest my own singularity (a singularity, which we shall see when we come to look at anxiety, has nothing at all to do with individuality, if we mean by the latter being different or unusual). Or, to put it in Heideggerโs more technical vocabulary, Daseinโs self is a modification of the โThey-self โ and not the other way around (BT: 168).
So strangely enough the answer to the question, โWho am I?โ is notย first of all an โIโ or a โself โ , because I do not live as an isolated subject which somehow has toย find its way back into the world. There is no fundamental ontological opposition between self and others. On the contrary, others already belong to very Being of Dasein. Being with others is not a secondary characteristic added onto my existence. I am already with others from the very beginning. The traditional philo- sophical problem of other minds is absurd because it presupposes that Dasein is a closed entity like a thing which is present-to-hand. Existentially speaking, the existence of others is not a problem at all, because by the very fact that I am in the world I am already involved with others. I do not have to prove they exist to make sense of them, because I cannot make sense of myself without them.
My original ontological relation to others Heidegger names as โBeing-withโ (Mitsein). Being-with is just as significant as Being-in in understanding the Being of Dasein. Just as we must understand the โinโ of Being-in specifically in an existential way, then we should also understand the โwithโ of Being-with. โWithโ here does not have a cat- egorical meaning, as one thing being next to another thing. The โIโ and the โOtherโ are not two things opposed to one another. Quite the contrary, I am with others precisely because we do not stand apart from one another. I am with others because we share the same concern with the world. Things cannot share a world in this way, just as the chair, in Heideggerโs previous analysis, cannot encounter the wall it is leaning against (BT: 81). I do not relate to others, there- fore, as a theoretical or social construct examined from the outside by an anthropologist or sociologist. Rather in my everyday involve- ment in the world, they are already there with me. As Heidegger writes in section twenty-six, even when I walk alongside aย field in the countryside, and nobody is there, others are still present as Being- with, because the boundaries of thisย field mattered to someone at
sometime, and my walk itself traces the contours of their concern (BT: 153). Thus, it is ridiculous to claim Dasein does not already belong to others in its very existing, because it can be alone. I can only be alone because I am already with others. Why would loneliness affect me so if this were not the case?
If I do encounter others already in my environment, this does not mean others have the same Being as things. Others, as those which already belong to my Being, are neither present nor ready-to-hand, rather they are like me. This is why, in section twenty-six, Heidegger will use the word โsolicitudeโ (Fรผrsorge) rather than โconcernโ to describe the specific nature of my relation to others (BT: 157). In my everyday existence, I am indifferent to the presence of others. I walk down the street and I hardly see them at all, just as I do not see the door I walk through every day unless it is locked against my expecta- tions. Such an indifferent relation to others, however, is still a relation, even if it is a privative one. I can only ignore others in this way because they are part of my everyday existence.
Heidegger also writes, however, that I can have a positive relation to others, where they are present to me, though not in the way that a thing is, and this positive relation has two forms: one, where I stand in or replace the otherโs possibilities; and two, where I free others for their own possibilities. It will not be entirely clear to us until the next section what Heidegger means by โpossibilityโ here, but it is perfectly clear what he means by standing in or freeing the other. If my purpose in writing this book is to release you from the effort of reading Heideggerโsย Being and Time, then it could be said I am standing in for you. If, on the contrary, my original intention was to enable you to understandย Being and Timeย better for yourself, then it might be argued I am freeing you to be yourself, rather than substituting your own understanding for mine. Solicitude also has its own way of seeing par- allel to the circumspection of concern where โone looks after othersโ, which Heidegger calls โconsideratenessโ and โforbearanceโ (BT: 159). Again such a โseeingโ should not be confused with theoretical knowl- edge. I do notย first of all know others, rather they matter to me, and only in this way would knowing something about them be significant at all.
Others also, and this is more predominantly the case, rule over the
possibilities of Dasein, but not as some particular of specific โOtherโ,
as in the case of solicitude. It is these others, which are always hazy and indistinct and really no one at all, which Heidegger calls the โTheyโ or the โAnyoneโ. I see myself as others see themselves (โWe take pleasure,โ as Heidegger writes, โand enjoy ourselves asย theyย take plea- sure; we read, see and judge about literature and art asย theyย see and judgeโ [BT: 164. Heideggerโs emphasis]). What is important, however, about these others is they are not anyone specific; they are just someone. I could not really point to them in the street and say it is they who are determining the way I engage with the world. On the contrary, these opinions and ways of living are just in the air with no one being responsible for them at all. This anonymity is inseparable from a โlevelling downโ of possibilities, because we cannot reallyย find the source for why everyone thinks or acts in this way so no one has to be accountable for their existence.34
In Daseinโs absorption and involvement in the world, in its com- parison of itself with those who share its world, it takes on the char- acteristic of the They. Rather than being itself it is this anonymous self. The who of Daseinโs existence, therefore, is not a self,ย first of all, but a โthey-self โ. I think, act and do what everyone else thinks, acts and does. Again we have to be very careful not to mistake this analysis for a moral crusade on Heideggerโs behalf. It is part of the very way Dasein exists that it is absorbed in the world, and also shares this world with others. The fact that I myself, for the most part, live my life as others do, without regard or introspection, belongs essentially to my Being. It is not a personal fault. It does mean, however, if I am to be myself and not a โthey-self โ (it is important to underline that being a โthey-self โ is a way to be me, and does not contradict the existential fact that existence is always โmineโ), then this will always be against the background of anonymous existence. The self is not given to Dasein. It is something it has to win. As I wrote at the beginning of this section, life is a drama and a struggle. It is a task to be accomplished and not merely a fait accompli. How such a possibility is possible, we can only see by the deepening of the analysis of Being-in-the-world through the description of moods and the understanding.
Moods, Understanding and Language
So far I have described Being-in-the-world through our involvement with equipment and our intimacy (indifferent for the most part) with
others. Both these ways of Being, however, are dependent on a more fundamental structure of existence. We remember from the previous chapter that the โbeing-inโ of Dasein is not the same as the โbeing-inโ of beings which are present-to-hand. The spatiality of Dasein is not geometrical, but lived. As when, for example, we speak of someone being close to us. We do not mean by this the smallness of the distance between us (except metaphorically), but that they are important to us.35ย Thus, someone on the other side of the world (existentially speaking) can be closer than the person sitting right next to us on the bus. The way in which equipment and others are related to me is therefore dependent on my own โpositionโ in the world. This position is, again, not a geometrical one, but belongs to my own way of exist- ing in the world. Heidegger calls it (evoking the literal German meaning of theย daย of Dasein) the โthereโ, which is to be grasped as โdisclosureโ (Erschlossenheit) (BT: 171).
When I relate to equipment and others, I reveal their Being (this is what Heidegger means when he occasionally says that Dasein frees beings). In so doing, I bring them into my world. Such a world is not a place on a map (at least not directly), but a horizon of intelligibility in which equipment and others make sense and have a presence for me. We can imagine (as long as we do not take this literally), the โthereโ of Dasein as an illuminated circle in which equipment and others are lighted up. Of course this luminescence is not solitary, but one which I share with others. None the less I have to, so to speak, live it for myself.
Such a circle is not,ย first of all, experienced through cognition. On the contrary, knowing in this sense is dependent on my world having already been revealed to me. I must live my world before I can know it in this limited way. My world as a whole, on the contrary, is revealed to me by moods. Knowledge directs itself to particular objects and persons in the world, but I cannot know my world as a whole as that which matters to me. This is not because I lack sufficient information, and if I only knew more I could do so. Rather, my world, as that in which I live, and in which equipment and others are intelligible to me, is not available to knowledge at all. If cognition refers to particular objects in the world as present-to-hand (even others), then moods reveal how the world is for me, when for example someone asks โHow are you?โ I am always in some mood or other, happy, bored or
miserable, and these moods bathe my whole experience of my world in a certain kind of light.36
What they show to me is that I am always attached to my world in one way or another. In other words, my world always affects me as a whole. I am not just happy, bored or miserable about this or that thing, rather my world as a whole is joyous, boring or miserable. Traditional philosophy, on the contrary, treats moods as merely a subjective colouring which have to be dispensed with if we really want to know what objects are, but this is precisely because it takes categorical Being, as we discussed earlier, to be the only way of Being.37
The way my world always affects me, and that I am attached to it before I have made any decision or choice to be so, Heidegger calls โthrownnessโ (Geworfenheit) (BT: 174). We have already come across this word before, when we thought about how the past colours our under- standing of Being, but now we can understand for theย first time the source of the weight of tradition.38ย It belongs to Daseinโs existence, as such, that it is always delivered over to its world which affects it, and it is this pull or drag of my world which is the ultimate force and power of the domination of the past.39ย It is not just a storehouse of facts which have happened, and which we might read about in books, but belongs to my present as the very fact of my existence โ that one is what one is and no other. Such a basic fact of existence (Heidegger calls it โfacticityโ (Faktizitรคt) to differentiate it from the mere objective facts about something) is not something that I can decide without con- ditions, but it still something I have decided to be (BT: 174). This means my โhaving beenโ, must, in some way, already pre-exist my immediate experience, even though it belongs to it and shapes its peaks and valleys. My cultural background forms my choices and decisions, but not from the outside in a determinate way. I have to be it for it to have any meaning at all. It is this irredeemable fact of my existence (I have not chosen but must choose) which my moods reveal to me, even though most of the time I relate to them in an evasive way. What moods reveal to me is my world as a whole, my attunement, or lack of it, with my world. But in a mood, my world is not revealed to me as something present-to-hand, an object of theoretical interest, but as an enigma. A mood is what I live, but always as something Iย find difficult to articulate (sometimes a hand gesture can say more about my mood than anything I say). This does not mean that moods
are less than knowledge, or even that objective cognition has anything to say about them. For if the world did not matter to me existentially, then why would I want to know anything specific about it (can one imagine a permanently bored Einstein)? I do not look at the world as a static camera might (or the camera only really looks at the world because it is a piece of equipment being used by me), butย first of all I am affected by it and then I look (a great photographer has a way of being affected by the world which others lack). The world is some- thing, which as a whole, matters to me, and about which I am con- cerned. In what way it matters to me is made manifest by a mood.
Because moods, as the primary way in which I relate to my world, are not to be thought cognitively, then we should not make the mistake of thinking that the second major characteristic of Daseinโs Being-in-the-world, โunderstandingโ (Verstehen) must be. Daseinโs understanding does not make good what moods lack. It is not a cate- gorical way of relating to the world, but accompanies every mood I have. We remember from the previous chapter that existence is to be understood as possibility.40ย It is not to be thought logically merely as the opposite to necessity, but ontologically the way in which Dasein is. My world is not just disclosed as a collection of facts, but as possibil- ities. Whatever situation Iย find myself in, there are always possibili- ties. It is the understanding which throws itself ahead into these possibilities as โprojectionโ (Entwurfย ) (BT: 185). This is not like some kind of plan or programme I have in advance and then apply to my experience of the world. Rather, I am already ahead of myself in the possible and understand myself in these terms. This is why Heidegger can say, even if it sounds paradoxical, Dasein is always more than just what it is. As what I am now, I am already what I am not because I have projected myself forward. Of course what I can or cannot do is not limitless. We are not speaking here of an empty abstract freedom, because I, as we have just seen, am thrown into a world which already determines, in a fundamental way, how I can be. On the other hand, I cannot simply abrogate my responsibility for myself, because I still have to take a stand on what I have become and the possibilities revealed there.
Linked to understanding is what Heidegger calls โinterpretationโ (Auslegung). It is the working out of the possibilities revealed to me by the understanding. Such a โworking outโ should again not be confused
with knowledge. Interpretation, as Heidegger describes it in section thirty-two, belongs to the ready-to-hand and the referential totality of the environment, and not to the present-to-hand (BT: 188โ95). The interpretation of possibilities is pragmatic and not theoretical. Heidegger writes in theย History of the Concept of Timeย that when a child asks me, โWhat is this thing?โ I answer by explaining its purpose and function.41ย Only when I have interpreted it in this way, or have under- stood the interpretation, is it possible for me to put it into words and define it in the limited way in which traditionally philosophy has tended to grasp the essence of things. Of course, interpreting the purpose and function of something is setting it within the general horizon of intelligibility of my world (in other words, its possibilities). This is why it is very important to get the relation between the under- standing and interpretation the right way around. In order to see something as something, the hammer as a tool which hammers in nails for example, I have to โseeโ the context (the relational whole) in which the activity of hammering nails would make sense (BT: 186). For me to see something as having a purpose or function, it already has to be part of my background understanding of my world, and this understanding is not at all similar to a cognitive grasp of a particular object.
One way we can make the distinction between interpretation and understanding, on the one hand, and cognition, on the other, more visible is through the fore-structure of interpretation (BT: 191โ2). Interpretation is never just a mere looking at something present-to- hand. Rather it looks both backwards and forwards: โbackwardsโ in the sense that it is shaped by โfacticityโ, and forwards by possibilities. The analogy here is with reading. I never come to a text presupposi- tionless. My reading is already shaped by both my prejudices and expectations. We cannot avoid this. Context-free knowledge is an illu- sion. Even the most abstract way of looking at something hides its own prejudices and expectations, because this belongs essentially to the way Dasein is.42ย Every interpretation supposes an understanding which guides it, but to complain this is a โvicious circleโ is to take logic to be the guide of existence, rather than existence the guide of logic. The problem with traditional metaphysics is that it thinks logic is true precisely because it believes it to be contextless (which it is not), and thus completely distorts the meaning of existence.
What then is the context of logic? Heidegger answers this question in section thirty-three (BT: 195โ203). He understands logic as โasser- tionโ (Aussage) which has three meanings (BT: 196โ7):
- โPointing outโ โ the original sense ofย logosย as โletting some thing be seen as itself โ which goes back to the way in which Heidegger described phenomenology in section seven (BT: 55โ8).
- Predicationโ โ a narrower meaning of assertion which is only possible because of this prior โpointing outโ.
- โCommunicationโ โ that which is pointed out is done so in such a manner that it is easily communicable to others.
If we make an assertion about something (to use Heideggerโs example, the hammer is too heavy [BT: 197]), then it ceases to be present to us as ready-to-hand, but becomes present-to-hand. When something is present-to-hand, we talk about it as a โwhatโ which has this or that property, and is therefore no longer part of our involvement with things and our intimacy with others. None the less, this โwhatโ, which we think is the true objective nature of the thing, has its origin in our prior engagement with the world. The hammer is already present to me before it is a subject with predicates. Heidegger describes assertion as a kind of โstepping backโ (BT: 197). When I make judgements about things, I have a restricted and narrow view of them. If my relation to things as present-to-hand has its original source in the ready-to-hand, then this is not true the other way around. The ready-to-hand never descends from the present-to-hand. My everyday involvement with the hammer is not a limitation of my cognitive grasp of something present-to-hand. If it were not already disclosed by the understanding, and then laid out by interpretation, I could not make any assertions about it (this is why the idea of context-free logic is absurd).
We might describe the history of philosophy, at least for Heidegger, as the illegitimate reversal of the relation between ready-to-hand and present-to-hand. It takes what is ontologically prior, our practical and everyday involvement with my world which matters to me, and makes it derivative of the narrow relation of judgement. Why this is so must have, as we have already discussed, had its origin in the way of Being of Dasein. The emphasis on logic as the only truth of things and the world (which the ancient Greek philosophers were perhaps theย first to
emphasise) is a anxiousย flight away from the messiness of the world, which is truer, even if it appears meaningless, than any supposedly true statement, with all its rigour and clarity.
One way we can see this is in the phenomenon of language. At the time of writingย Being and Time, Heidegger is not at all part of what has been called retrospectively the โlinguistic turnโ in philosophy, where what is real is merely a projection of language. On the contrary, lan- guage is merely a tool through which I express my understanding and interpretation of the world. The โabout whichโ that language expresses is not itself linguistic. Why logic, in the restricted sense as judgement, becomes so dominant is that its โabout whichโ is extremely limited and thereby easily communicable because the thing it speaks about is abstracted from the complex web of existential relations which actually give it meaning and which in turn cannot be reduced to any logical statement. There is something bizarre, as a practice, of philosophers pointing to chairs and tables, and asking what they are, because we can only really understand them in relation to a world in which they have a purpose or a function, and this world, as is hope- fully becoming clear, is not a โwhatโ at all.
To think of language as a tool is to think of it pragmatically. What am I doing when I speak? This leads us to the third structure of Daseinโs Being-there, which is โdiscourseโ (Rede). When I speak to another, what I say communicates a shared world which is already intelligible. Such a shared world is not in the words themselves, but what the words express. Language has its ontological possibility in Dasein and not the other way around. To be able to listen and speak to someone we must already be with them in some way or another. It is perfectly possible to imagine an animal or a machine speaking words, but if we do not already share a common meaningful world, these words would not really say anything at all.43ย It is because speaking with one another is the essence of language (we must liberate, Heidegger says, grammar from logic [BT: 208]), and not the words spoken, that what is important about language can become listening and being silent. For in this way, I might be more attentive to what is being spoken about (the matter at hand), than just to the words themselves and to the other who is speaking. What happens for the most part, however, is โidle chatterโ (which we shall look at in the next chapter).44ย The fundamen- tal โabout whichโ which any true conversation concerns itself with gets
replaced by the mere definition of words. So, for example, in reading this book (and Heidegger like most philosophers is mistrustful of writing for this very reason), rather than thinking about what is trying to be thought (the question of Being) in your own genuine way, you are only interested in a glossary of definitions which can be repeated in an essay or exam. This is not thinking but merely the transmission of information when no doubt some time in the future no one really knows what was being thought in theย first place.
A genuine conversation is a true one. It discloses my world both as
involvement with things and intimacy with others. As such, it also dis- closes who I am, for I am nothing but involvement and intimacy. What we mean by โtruthโ here, however, is not the truth of a mere judgement, as when, for example, I say that all bachelors are men. Moods, understanding and language are all linked together by a more fundamental meaning of truth as disclosure, which Heidegger does not really describe in detail until section forty-four ofย Being and Time. This is why, rather than waiting till later, it is better to explain it now.
Truth and Reality
Traditionally we think of truth as agreement. We say that a statement is true because it agrees with a state of affairs in the world. I say, โIt is raining,โ and when you look out of the window it really is raining, so my statement is true. Like with most things which appear obvious, the more we investigate them the less simple they are. Heideggerโs approach to the problem of truth in this section is twofold, and it mirrors the method ofย Being and Timeย as a whole. One part is histori- cal, to remind us that this common sense view of truth comes from a tradition, which in fact has a much more ambiguous and complex understanding of truth; and the other is phenomenological, which attempts to describe the experience of truth as disclosure, and thereby loosen the assumptions and prejudices of this tradition.
As Heidegger remarks at the very start of this section the question of truth and being have always gone together in philosophy (BT: 256). Originally, their association was thought through disclosure (which it should not surprise us Heidegger wants to retrieve), but this insight was overlaid by the logical conception of truth, whoseย first formula- tion is to be found in Aristotle (though, as always with the case of Aristotle for Heidegger, what he himself begins becomes watered
down as it trickles through philosophical history). It is this logical con- ception which is the basis of truth as agreement. Yet the more we think about agreement, the more puzzling it seems. Although the existence of the statement is obvious enough and the object it is sup- posed to agree with, what is it that allows them to agree with one another? Is it something in the statement, or in the object itself ? But if they are two different kinds of beings (nobody thinks that a state- ment is the same as a thing), what allows them to agree at all?
Heideggerโs response to these questions is neither toย find a better theory of correspondence, nor even to dismiss this theory, but to show that this conception must have its basis in a more fundamental expe- rience of truth. Our previous discussion of the sections on under- standing, interpretation and assertion should already make this dependence clear to us. Logical statements (whether true or false) are assertions and they, as we have already seen, are dependent upon a prior uncovering of things in the world, their original disclosure, whose source is the Being of Dasein.
Heidegger unpacks the hidden ontology of the traditional concep- tion of truth through a phenomenological example (BT: 260โ1). Let us imagine someone has their back turned to the wall and they make the assertion, โThe picture on the wall is crooked.โ At what point does this assertion become true? Does not the truth happen when they turn around and see that the picture really is crooked? What Heidegger stresses is that truth happens not in the statement nor even in the head of the person who utters it, but when the picture reveals itself as it is to the person who is standing there. If the picture did not show or manifest itself to me, then how could I say anything about it at all? The possibility of the statement being true or false, in the logical sense, therefore, is dependent on the phenomenological (in the way Heidegger describes it in section seven) experience of uncovering (Entdeckend). This uncovering, in turn, however, is only possible because the world as such is disclosed to me. Truth is not,ย first of all, a description of statements, but a way of Being in the world. If things were not present to me in my world, then I would not be able to make statements about them. This originally, Heidegger asserts, is how the Greeks understood the phenomenon of truth, before it was overlaid by its logical conception. The Greek word for truth,ย aletheia, literally means โunforgettingโ, โun-concealingโ, or โunhiddennessโ (BT: 262).45
If truth is a way of Being-in-the-world, then it can only belong to a being who has a world. The only being which has a world is Dasein. That I can make judgements and assertions about things in the world must mean that they are โthereโ in some way or other. That they are โthereโ, however, is dependent on a more primordial โthereโ which is the region of disclosure. Such a โspaceโ, as we have already seen, is not itself a being. It is neither present-to-hand, nor ready-to-hand, but is the world in which things are intelligible. Things are present to me because they are meaningful, but they are only meaningful because they have their place within the overall context of my world. This is why Heidegger can write that Dasein exists in the truth (BT: 263). Does this not sound dangerously like relativism? Things are only true because we experience them so? To answer this question we must turn back briefly to the section that immediately precedes this one, โDasein, Worldhood and Realityโ (BT: 244โ56).
One of the oldest questions of philosophy is whether the world exists or not. Which philosophy student has not been seduced by Descartesโ thought experiment that the world might be nothing but a dream? How can we respond to this question? Certainly not by attempting to prove the world does exist. Some philosophical ques- tions can only be answered by showing they are badly formulated, rather than by coming up with an alternative answer. The possibility of imagining the world to beย fiction has its source in a metaphysics which is ontologically false. I can only imagine myself separate from the world, if my only relation to it is representational, but it is pre- cisely such a conception which is prejudicial. Why must I conceive of my Being in this way? Am I not, as Heidegger has shown us, already in the world, and does not the possibility of even coming up with such absurd philosophical fantasies have its basis there?
Heideggerโs response to this problem means that it is difficult to place him in the split between realism and idealism which has char- acterised philosophy since Descartes, and around which it seems per- manently to oscillate (though he does say there is more truth to idealism than realism [BT: 251]). The world is not a representation, but nor is it external to me as the aggregate of natural things. What is common to idealism and realism is that they both lack a proper ontological understanding of the world. I am not an element within the world, but nor is it apart from me. On the contrary, there is no
such thing as the world, if we think of it as a being (whether this being is real or ideal). The world, rather, is a way of Being of Dasein. It is not a substance at all, but a verb. Only out of this way of Being can the question of reality of the world itself arise, but it immediately dis- torts how Dasein actually exists in a world. Both realism and idealism (even if their solutions might be very different) treat Dasein and the world as though they were something present-to-hand, which then, in a second moment, have to be stuck back together again after being separated. Heidegger is not about to provide a solution to this age-old problem. Rather, he shows that such issues are absurd because of the way the problem is formulated. I am already in a world. I am my world. The world is me. Ontologically speaking, the world and I are inseparable. Not because the world and I are the same thing, but because Being-in-the-world is what it means to be the kind of being I am, and it is only through such an understanding that any beings are accessible at all
Anxiety, Death and Guilt
What I cannot face is the meaninglessness of my life. I will die and do so alone. What does it matter to the community of the human race that I have died? Perhaps my friends and family might remember me, but they too will die. So I need, while I live, to forget my death. I mustย fill this meaninglessness with significance. I fall back into the world and busy myself with things and others. I speak. Each moment of speech is the irruption of meaning into world. It is as though the world begins again with my birth. In itself, however, this redemption is a false one. For what the world promises me, it also takes away. Rather than a true dialogue with things and others (or more precisely only with others, since it is only through them that I can have an authentic relation with things), I am surrounded by anonymous dis- course which comes from nowhere. I am addressed constantly. My life is saturated by signs (we live in a world of communication), but I cannot speak to them. I only consume them. How do I escape this whirlwind? By facing what I want to avoid: the meaninglessness of my life.
The importance of anxiety and death to Heideggerโs analysis is that they are not morbid phenomena. They are, in fact, what make
us truly human as opposed to mere animals. So far, he argues, we have only described Daseinโs inauthentic existence. Now we have to show what it means to be authentic. This is not becauseย Being and Timeย is some kind of philosophical life style book (though philosophy ought to affect how we lives our lives), but it does have important method- ological reasons. We remember from the very beginning that Heideggerโs question is the meaning of Being in general and not just the Being of Dasein. The analytic of Dasein is merely a means to end. It is because Dasein is the only being whose Being is an issue for it that it is the clue to the meaning of Being in general. Yet if such a ques- tion is the key to the meaning of Being, how does Daseinโs Being become an issue for it? My Being certainly is not a question for me if I am absorbed in the world. It can only be so if I break with its fasci- nation and temptation. There must be a life condition for the possi- bility of philosophy and the analysis of anxiety and death is the description of why something like the writing ofย Being and Timeย could have happened at all and even that you might be interested in reading it. This is not just a biological fact (dogs and stones cannot read), but an existential or interpretative one. Why is it that you are interested in the meaning of your life as a whole? And of course there are others who are not, who just want to be absorbed into the world as we all are to some extent and have to be.
This question brings us to another methodological issue for Heidegger and one that is more pertinent to the writing ofย Being and Time. How is it possible to grasp Daseinโs Being as whole, rather than as fragmented into different possibilities and projects? Again, the reason that Heidegger wants to view Daseinโs Being as whole has to do with the overall question ofย Being and Time, which is the meaning of Being in general. By being able to grasp Dasein as whole, we will also be able to see the ultimate horizon of its Being. This horizon is time, which is the fundamental topic of the second division, and which will be explained in theย final part of the book. Of course, we have been talking about time all along, but only then will it become vivid to us. This part will be divided into three sections: theย first will examine falling and anxiety; the second, death; and the last guilt and resoluteness. The material here straddles theย first and second divisions ofย Being and Time, and covers what we left out in the previous part. It moves from inauthenticity to authenticity, because it is only the latter
which allows us to grasp the deep temporal structure of human exis- tence and, since it is only we who discourse about Being, why it too can only be spoken about through time.
Falling and Anxiety
In the previous part, we jumped over Heideggerโs description of the everyday experience of Being-in-the-world, so as to explain the exis- tential meaning of truth, because I believed it sat better with the order of explanation ofย Being and Time. Now, however, we have to return to this experience, otherwise it will not be clear to us what it is that anxiety, so to speak, goes against, and in so doing how it reveals the structure of Daseinโs Being, which Heidegger calls โcareโ (Sorge).
Dasein is in the world through moods, understanding and lan- guage, but how are these lived in the everyday world? We remember from the previous part that for Heidegger what is essential in language is not the words spoken but what is spoken about. In speaking to others (and even to ourselves) what matters is what it is we are talking about which reveals something about our world. This interpretive power of language, as opposed to the mere fact of words, Heidegger calls โdiscourseโ (Rede). Do we really, however, talk this way for the most part? Would it not be truer to say that on the whole we simply talk, and what it is we are talking about does not really matter at all? When I speak to people I meet on the street or at work, I am mostly just passing the time of day. If you were to ask me what it was we spoke about, I really would not be able to tell you, or if I did, I would say it was not important. This is not to say I do not have genuine conversations, but they are rare in comparison.
The common and everyday way that we talk together Heidegger describes in section thirty-five as โidle chatterโ (Gerede) and it is the opposite of discourse (BT: 211โ14). Such chatter is the basis of my everyday involvement with others. It is the medium which glues us together. We traffic together through words which are no longer about anything at all and it is because of them we end up interpret- ing ourselves as having the same interests and desires as everyone else. This is so because no one really knows any more what these words are about. It is as though the endless chatter from all the different media has completely blocked out any sense of what might or might not be important. Such is the source of the feeling we have that, despite the
fact we have more information than perhaps any other generation we actually know less. This also explains the other phenomenon of every- day absorption in the world which Heidegger describes as โcuriosityโ (Neugier), in section thirty-six (BT: 214โ17), because what is talked and written about no longer has any basis in something significant. The public world is one of endless curiosity, because there is nothing to stop the gaze. Every experience is an equal to any other experience, because no experience is sufficiently important in itself. Reality becomes a spectacle of consumption. Rather than being directly involved with things and intimate with others, I distance myself from them (curiosity is an exaggerated form of โde-severanceโ)46ย and simply devour them up from afar. It is not that they matter to me, because it is unlikely that I really know them at all and I certainly do not have any serious engagement with them. All I see is their image which begins to take over every aspect of my reality, so that even in my conversations with others all I talk about is the image.
If idle chatter and curiosity are the everyday forms of discourse and understanding, then the last form, โambiguityโ (Zweideutigkeit) is not a negative corollary of moods (BT: 217โ19). This is because moods (whether negative or positive) are always revelatory for Heidegger. They tell me something about the world in which I exist. This is why talking, when it is not serious, is aย fleeing away from what moods reveal. Ambiguity is not a mood, but a confusion of under- standing or interpretation. The spectacle is so effervescent that I no longer know what is important or not. What is spoken about, dis- cussed and communicated is so noisy that I can no longer discern what is worth listening to. Because I cannot make out what is worth seeing, listening or doing, then I end up following what everyone else is seeing, listening to and doing. Yet when I ask someone why they are looking at, listening to and doing this, they equally have no more reason to do so than I have. What is ambiguous about this phenome- non is that its source is Being with others, but at the same time this type of relation to others is what prevents me from having an authen- tic relation to them.
We might say, however, that this ambiguity extends over the whole of the everyday. It is very important we do not misunderstand this description as a censure, otherwise Heidegger will just end up sound- ing like a reactionary conservative of the worst kind (there is no doubt
some think he is so). This is not an ontic description of an age gone bad, but an ontological investigation of the kind of being which Dasein is. The everyday is not something, therefore, we should get rid of, or even could do so, but belongs to what it is to be Dasein. It is therefore a positive ontological phenomenon (other beings can never experience the everyday). Two important consequences follow from this: one, that Heidegger is attempting to save the everyday inย Being and Timeย against traditional metaphysics which tends to see it as some- thing which has to be transcended in order to reach true knowledge; and two, that the authentic relationship to things and others in the world must have its source in the everyday, and not the other way around. In other words, Heidegger is not seeking to get beyond the everyday, but to show how the everyday is already involved, because of the way which Dasein is, in what cannot be experienced as the everyday. We can already see this, for example, in Heideggerโs description of curiosity. If we were not curious at all, then there could not be any possible involvement with things or intimacy with others. Even cognition, which is a particular way of seeing, has its basis in everyday curiosity (BT: 215). Of course, if we fail to understand the ontological roots of curiosity in Daseinโs Being, then it can become the endless and meaningless form which Heidegger describes.
Daseinโs occupation by rather than in the everyday Heidegger calls, in section thirty-eight, โfallingโ (Verfallen) (BT: 219โ24). It belongs to the way that Dasein is that it is wholly and completely absorbed, dis- tracted and bemused by the world. The โinโ of โinauthenticityโ should, therefore, not be understood negatively. Dasein is not itself, when it has โfallenโ into the world. Quite the contrary, this is just how it is. But in so being, the phenomenon of the world remains invisible to it. Not the world, as a collection of events and happenings, which of course it is obsessed and consumed by precisely because it has so fallen, but the worldhood of the world, what makes it possible, as part of its own Being, that there is a world for it to be absorbed by in theย first place. Here for theย first time we can begin to understand the importance of the mood of anxiety for Heidegger (again remembering it is always moods which reveal the world as a whole to us). It makes visible what is invisible in fallenness.
Heidegger says that what is lacking in our everyday Being-in-the- world is a โground to stand onโ (BT: 168). We might be tempted,
especially because of Heideggerโs own political decisions, to interpret such a lack as part of the ideology of โblood and soilโ, but we would be quite wrong to do so.47ย Yes, Heidegger will be searching, in his description of authenticity, for a ground for Daseinโs Being, but what we will discover, and this is what is so strange and unsettling, is that this ground is in fact nothing. We therefore have to distinguish between the groundlessness of everyday existence in which Dasein, like a leaf in the wind, is blown in this direction and that, and the experience of nothingness which is genuine to anxiety. It is because at bottom Daseinโs Being is nothing, that its total absorption in any world is ontologically impossible. Ontically, the everyday isย first, but ontologically it is the nothing which is fundamental. The nothing is what makes any world possible. It is, so to speak, the โspaceโ (existen- tially understood) which it occupies, but it is also at the same time what makes any Dasein singular, because the origin of this nothing is its own Being. This means that no Dasein is wholly synonymous with the particular cultural world in which it lives. The difference between a world (Japanese, English and so on), and the worldhood of the world is precisely this nothing, and it is this which individuates Dasein (the nothing is not a definition of Dasein, but a way of Being which is specific to Dasein). The fact that existence is always โmineโ, is only because at the heart of my existence there is nothing (in other words, I am not reducible to any predicate which is said of me).48
This all sounds very peculiar at the moment, but every creative philosopher, precisely because he has to seek out a problem in a new way to make us think, pushes at the limits of what any language, at a particular point in historical time, can communicate. Who does not struggle with Aristotle and Kant even today? A commentary would be useless if it pretended philosophy were simple and could be easily digested. To seek to do so would be even more bizarre in relation to Heidegger, for it would be to reduce his work to idle chatter, curios- ity and ambiguity. None the less, it is my endeavour in this part to explain what this nothing means, and we shall begin to do so with the mood of anxiety which is described by Heidegger in section forty (BT: 228โ35).
Anxiety is a fundamental mood which reveals the worldhood of the world to us, but it does soย first of all negatively. For we must remember that Heidegger has only just described to us what everyday
Being-in-the-world is. Whatever it is that anxiety reveals must be what everyday existence is inย flight from. What itย flees from the phenome- nologist must follow. What Dasein is inย flight from, though it might not know this itself, is itself. But what is this โitself โ? Is it like a thing in the world, or a person? What am Iย fleeing, when I say that I amย fleeing myself ? Heidegger would respond that I am trying to escape my uniqueness or singularity. I want to be defined like a thing, or live like other people. Before we, however, try to understand what this self might be which I am trying to avoid, I have to think of the status of this mood itself. Here Heidegger distinguishes fear from anxiety. Fear, which he described previously, is always fear of something in the world which threatens my existence (BT: 179โ82). Anxiety, on the contrary, has no object. I am not anxious about this thing or that person in my world, but my world as such. It is to get away from this anxiety about my existence that Iย flee from the question of myself and absorb myself in the world. Precisely because it is not this or that which I am anxious about, theย first quality of the mood of anxiety is indefiniteness (BT: 231). It is the indefinite object of anxiety whichย fills me with horror such that I shrink away from it and busy myself with the world.
What the mood of anxiety reveals, if I were to follow it, is that my world which I occupy myself with (the world of the ready and present- to-hand) rests on nothing. What conceals the worldhood of the world is the things and people I relate to, and with which and whom I busy my time. All this coming and going conceals the ontological basis of my world, but occasionally and perhaps without premeditation, anxiety can strip all this way, dissolving them into a fog of nothing- ness, such that for a moment my world as a whole is revealed. Worldhood, as opposed to a world, cannot itself be something, either present or ready-to-hand. This is why Heidegger says that it comes from โnowhereโ and is โnothingโ (BT: 231). What is ontologically nothing, however, is not the same as what is ontically nothing. When I say that something is not, I just mean it does not exist. But when Heidegger says Dasein exists ontologically as nothing, then he does not mean just that it does not exist. Rather, we have to understand Being as nothing positively. It is not an assertion about things but a way of Being. Dasein is nothing if we understand โisโ existentially and not categorically. It is nothing because it is not a thing, and when we
say the worldhood of the world is nothing this is because the onto- logical origin of any particular ontic world is the Being of Dasein whose Being is neither present nor ready-to-hand. Metaphysics fails, as we have seen, because it wants to define Dasein as special kind of thing, but it is literally โno-thingโ at all.
This is why we can also think of the nothing in terms of possibili- ties, because the possible is how we understand the Being of Dasein. When I am absorbed in the world, I worry about this or that possi- bility. Am I a good enough philosophy teacher or student and so on? But this is not what I am anxious about. Just as I am not anxious about this or that thing or person in the world, so too am I not anxious about any specific possibility. On the contrary, what makes me anxious is the being possible as such. Every possibility exists, which I could actualise or not, in the sea of the possible which is nothing. This is not nihilism, because such an attitude exists in relation to specific values which belong to particular world. Nihilism, therefore, is one way of being occupied by a world, ofย fleeing from the nothing which you are. Anxiety, instead, throws me back to myself not so I should be this or that person, but so that I should relate to my possibilities as my own, and I can only do so from out of the nothingness which is at the heart of my existence. Every time I say here there is something which indi- viduates me (my spectacular wit, for example), then I am lying, for what I utter are common properties. What individuates me is nothing. The greatest temptation is toย fill this nothing with something, but it is a temptation which belongs to Dasein because it is nothing. Authenticity for Heidegger is not being this or that person, actualis- ing this or that possibility, rather it is facing the nothingness which is at the heart of your existence as nothing and holding fast to it. The status of this nothing will become clearer when we examine the following sections on death, the call of conscience and guilt.
Being towards Death
The importance of death for Heidegger is that it reveals, in the sharpest way possible, the particular distinctive nature of the Being of Dasein. But we might think, before we arrive at theย first chapter of division two ofย Being and Time, that we have already achieved this insight. Does not Heidegger tell us after the description of anxiety that we now understand the Being of Dasein through the unified
structure of care? Ahead of advancing into the detail of Heideggerโs investigation of death, let us ask ourselves, therefore, what this struc- ture is, and why he still felt it necessary to write the second division ofย Being and Time, even though the Being of Dasein seems now fully revealed.
Heidegger tells us in section forty-one that Daseinโs Being should be grasped as a totality (BT: 235). It is this totality which is revealed by anxiety. I am anxious about my Being as a whole and not some- thing in the world. But what is this whole? Heidegger typifies it by the three directions of Daseinโs Being. One is towards being thrown into the world (facticity); the other is towards my possibilities (existence); and both demonstrate that I always exist alongside other beings within the world (fallenness or falling). These three together make up what Heidegger calls โcareโ which he glosses as follows: โThe Being of Dasein means ahead-of-itself-Being-already in-(the world) as Being- alongside (entities encountered within-the-world)โ (BT: 237). All this sounds very abstract at the moment and it reads merely as a definition of Daseinโs Being rather than something it has to accomplish. It is not until we come to the chapters on time in division two (and which we will discuss in the next part) that we get any real understanding of what this unity might be. Even before we get there, however, there is a more immediate problem. For, as Heidegger begins the chapter on death, does it not belong to the way which Dasein is that it cannot be a whole because it always dies? Either I am alive, and therefore not complete, since there is something ahead of me, or I am dead, but then there is nothing there to experience it.
Why should this be such a problem for Heidegger? We must remember the aim of his book from the very beginning is to reawaken the question of the meaning of Being in general. The only being whose Being is an issue for it is Dasein, but if I cannot grasp my Being as a whole (not just as a disconnected series of events or happenings), then how can my Being be an issue for me? If it cannot, then the ques- tion of Being is everything Heidegger says it has become at the begin- ning ofย Being and Time, empty, trivial and indefinable. Is the language of totality, whole and unity, however, appropriate to Dasein as aย finite being? In what sense can my life be a whole, when it always ends in death? Heidegger is going to answer this question, as he tends to do, in a roundabout way. He is,ย first of all, going to suggest that a certain
way of speaking about a whole is not suitable to Dasein, but if we understand existentially, then it is.
When we talk about the end or totality of Dasein, then we are not speaking about it in the same way we might speak about something present-to-hand as having an objective limit. Death is not an end in this way. Of course, we have a tendency to think of death as though it were. We might imagine our lives like a line which begins with our birth and ends with our death, but it is exactly for this reason that we end up with the paradox that Dasein either is and is incomplete, or is not and complete. If I exist, then I am still โnot-yetโ, because there are possibilities ahead of me, or there are no more possibilities, but in that case I am dead. How can I experience my whole life and still be alive? We might think, Heidegger offers in section forty-seven, that we can answer this dilemma through the death of others (BT: 281โ5). I cannot experience my own death, but I can experience theirs. But in death is not the other just a corpse and therefore a thing? I might reply that the deceased is not just a thing, otherwise why would we have funeral rites? But even then do I really experience the death of the other? Is not the death of the other part of my life, because they were someone who mattered to me, rather then theirs? I no more experi- ence the transition from life to death through the other than I do in my own life. This brings Heidegger to an important conclusion (one which is really jumping ahead of his argument) that we have to face death alone: โDying is something that every Dasein itself must take upon itself at the timeโ (BT: 284).
I say Heidegger might have got ahead of himself here, because it
could appear that he means Dasein has to die alone, which is mani- festly absurd since many people do not do so. Such criticism, however, profoundly misunderstands the significance of death inย Being and Time. It is primarily concerned with death as a possibility and not as an actu- ality. Interest in the latter is how everyday existence avoids its existen- tial significance. Before Heidegger comes to this, however, he still wants sharply to distinguish, in section forty-eight, the end of Dasein from other ways in which we might speak about ends (BT: 285โ90). He spends so much time going through these distinctions because we continually fail to understand Daseinโs Being as existence, and confuse it with the Being of things which we encounter in the world (a confu- sion whose source, as we know, is Dasein itself as fallenness).
As long as I exist, I exist in the possible, in the โnot-yetโ, because there are still things to do. This not yet is not a lack which is thenย filled to make Dasein complete. This is to imagine Dasein as composite to which something needs to be added in order to make it whole. But I am what I am because of my โnot-yetsโ, not despite them. Our con- fusion arises here because we are thinking of Dasein as something present-to-hand which is missing some external part which only needs to be added to it in order for it to be whole, in the way, to use Heideggerโs example, we might think that a debt is outstanding until it is paid offย (BT: 286). But my end, my death, is not outstanding in this way. Perhaps the more appropriate example, Heidegger adds, is that of the fruit whose โnot yet ripenessโ belongs to what it is, rather than something which is appended to it from the outside (BT: 287โ8). But even this similarity is only superficial. For the ripeness of the fruit completes it. It is, to use the more Aristotelian language, the actuali- sation of its potentiality, itsย final cause. Death is not myย final cause. Does my death fulfil my purpose? Is not Heidegger right to suggest that most people die unfulfilled (BT: 288)?
The difference between death as a โnot-yetโ of Dasein, and these other processes, whether of a sum which is added to, or a course which is completed or not, is that the latter is always a case of actual- isation, whereas the former always remains open as a possibility. The debt is actually paid offย or not, the fruit actually ripens or it does not. But my death, which has not happened yet, is not experienced by me as an actuality, but as a permanent possibility. Of course, as Heidegger will later point out, my death can be treated as an actual- ity, but only from the outside and not by me, because it is the very pos- sibility of my impossibility. I think of it as an actuality because I see it as a fact which happens externally. Heidegger does not deny this. I die just like everything else does. But I do not just die; I can also live my death. I, already whilst I am alive, can have a relation to my death. But this death is now not an actuality, but a possibility. I am aware that at any moment it is possible I can die. The authentic relation to death is the relation to this possibility and not to its actuality.
The difference between death as an actuality (true of all things, even the universe) and death as a possibility is what Heidegger makes explicit by the phrase, โBeing-towards-deathโ (Sein-zum-Tode) which he distinguishes from โBeing-at-an-endโ (BT: 289). Death, in theย first
case, is not something which happens to me at the end of my life, rather it is that towards which I am already directed at the very instant of my birth, because it is always possible at any moment of my life. This is not to deny, as Heidegger remarks in the following section forty-nine, that there cannot be other kinds of investigation of death (such as in biology or anthropology), but they always treat death as a fact, whereas it is only death as a possibility which reveals the unique Being of Dasein (BT: 291โ3).
Let us look more deeply at what Heidegger means by death as a possibility in sectionย fifty (BT: 293โ6). It is not enough to say death is impending, for there are many possibilities, as Heidegger indicates, which are so, like a nearing storm or waiting for a friend. What is unique about the possibility of death is that it throws Dasein back upon its own possibility of Being. This is because, unlike any other possibility, it is the one possibility which strips me of all others. This is what Heidegger means when he says death is the โpossibility of the absolute impossibility of Daseinโ (BT: 294).49ย As such, it discloses to Dasein the whole of its Being as possible. For in being aware of my impending death (and I am so through the mood of anxiety and not cognitively), all my other possibilities, my relations to things and others, are stripped away. I understand that everything which they stand upon is fragile and transitory, for I could die at any moment, and all of this would disappear. This is precisely why the everyday relation to death attempts to avoid this insight and it does so by trans- forming death into an actuality. It is thought of as an event in the world, whether it concerns one death or many; someone close, or strangers far away. As Heidegger says in sectionย fifty-one, there is a minimal recognition of death in this opinion, but it pushes death away as a possibility which might happen to me (BT: 296โ9). I know that I will die, but this is an anonymous fact which happens to every- one (and in this way to no one). I think of death as an actuality which occurs at the end of my life, and not as an impending possibility which can happen at any moment. I am no longer anxious about my death as a future possibility which reveals my life as a whole, but fear death as an event and wonder how I might avoid it or prolong my life, even though this life might be perfectly meaningless; or, if I have the courage, even though I am meant to be completely indifferent to it.
Everyone knows they will die, but such certainty avoids the exis- tential import of Being-towards-death. We say this to ourselves so we do not have to face our own death as a possibility. It is just one more fact of life. We can be certain about the empirical fact of death, but this is not the same as being certain about the possibility of our own death. True, we know we will die, but this should not be confused with some kind of existential composure. On the contrary, existentially speaking, death is always uncertain, because as Heidegger writes, it is โpossible at any momentโ (BT: 258). Empirically certain, existentially uncertain, death reveals the precarious nature of my life. It is this transience which is covered over by my everyday occupations. Iย fill in time so as to conceal the nothingness which lies at its heart. I imagine my existence as something permanent, substantial, like a thing. It is not death as a fact which is terrifying, because everything dies and there is even something consoling about that thought. What is far more disturbing is the relation between life and death in a life which understands it can end at any moment and whose future, therefore, is always held out into its own disappearance. Such a recognition, which is a disclosure of my whole life, affects every one of my possibilities now. In terms of their content, they might not be any different. I might still be a teacher of philosophy, but how I relate to this content will be very different indeed.
What such a different relation might be is the topic of the next section in the description of the authentic attitude towards death, but it is also the subject of the next part, on the call of conscience, guilt and resoluteness (BT: 304โ11). If the pull of everyday life is so pow- erful, how is it possible to have an authentic regard for our own death as a permanent possibility which cannot be avoided? Just as was the case in anxiety, we have to look at what it is Dasein isย fleeing away from when it avoids understanding its own death. It is not death as such, as we have just seen, since everyone recognises its inevitability, but the possibility of death. An authentic attitude towards death, therefore, understands it as a possibility, but in so doing its whole rela- tion to its life is completely transformed.
Usually we think of possibility in terms of the primacy of actuality. Something is possible because it can be actualised and not the other way around. In Heideggerโs language, it is either ready or present-to- hand. But death is not a possibility in this way. Being-towards-death is
not about actualising death as a possibility, otherwise suicide would be the most authentic decision in the face of death. It is not about mor- bidly wondering about how my death might happen, but facing up to its permanent possibility, and how such a constant threat affects my life as a whole. At this point in his analysis, Heidegger distinguishes between โexpectationโ (Erwarten) and โanticipationโ (Vorlaufen) (BT: 306). When I expect something, I am imagining its realisation. When I anticipate, on the other hand, I am still holding open its possibility. In German,ย Vorlaufenย literally means โrunning aheadโ. I do not run ahead into death by actualising it, but by understanding the possibility of death as that which is the most imminent possibility of my life. There is nothing to actualise in this vision, because death, as we have seen, is the possibility of impossibility, and therefore is unlike any other.
It is not sufficient, however, to say I can anticipate my own death as a possibility for me to be authentic. There has to be a disclosure. In this vision, I see I am lost in the They. Only now do I realise what Heidegger means when he says every Dasein must die alone. What my anticipation of my death as a possibility reveals to me is my life. Not life in general, but the life I am living now. As I sit here wasting my time, wondering why my life is going nowhere, it is possible, through anxiety, that I can suddenly anticipate my own death. What if I were to die now watching this rubbish on television; would I really have lived a life worth living? To give meaning to our life is to antici- pate our own death. This is what Heidegger means by โfreedomโ (BT: 311). It is not the arbitrary choice of any possibility (and as thrown beings arbitrary choices are aย fiction), but choosing who you already are, but this time as your own choice and not just because others have chosen for you. None of this is a cry for individualism, since what it means to be you is to be intimately connected to things and others (I am only me because of them, and not despite them), but it is to have a โfreeโ relation to them rather than a trapped one.
The Call of Conscience, Guilt and Resoluteness
Heidegger says at the end of the chapter on death that he has described what it would mean to be authentic, but not how anyone might achieve it (BT: 311). The next part, and the sections which follow, are meant to answer this question. We now know that for the most part Dasein exists as They exist. Being a self, therefore, is not a
metaphysical construction, a property of a thing called Dasein, but an achievement and accomplishment. But how actually do I carry it through when the temptation to absorb and involve myself in the everyday world is so powerful? There must be, Heidegger says, some- thing externally which forces Dasein out of its self-satisfaction and comfort in the world. He labels it the โcall of conscienceโ (Ruf des Gewissens). As we shall see this โoutsideโ is in fact internal to Dasein. It calls to itself out of the gravitational pull of the They. What this call bears witness to is Daseinโs guilt, and in recognising it Dasein is res- olute. โCall of conscienceโ, โguiltโ, โresolutenessโ, all this sounds very theological, but as elsewhere inย Being and Time, Heidegger is adamant this is an ontological analysis and presupposes no faith or belief in God. What we have to do is understand these expressions on their own terms and judge if they are phenomenologically accurate. Let usย first examine, therefore, what Heidegger means by the call of con- science in the following three sections (BT: 315โ25).
The call of conscience belongs to discourse. It, as we have already
seen, is the way in which Dasein is disclosed to itself. It belongs to the understanding, and the understanding to the possibilities of Dasein.50ย Because understanding is discourse, it is not a theoretical judge- ment about possibilities, but a listening or hearing. Of course, what Heidegger means by listening or hearing here is not empirical, but an ontological disclosure. For it to be possible for me to break out of the restricted possibilities which are given to me by the They, I must be able to โhearโ the possibility of Being myself. What I am responding to is the call of conscience. Such a call does not have any information. Nor does it communicate anything particular to me. On the contrary, in relation to the noise of the everyday world, it is silent. It is not a vocal call at all, but an awakening of myself from out of the bewitch- ment of the world.
If the call of conscience belongs to discourse, then there must be something it discloses. What is the subject of the call of conscience? The subject is Dasein who is called to be a self as a way of Being. Being a self, therefore, is a vocation, but it is only so because I can be called to it. Dasein is the caller and the called. We should not confuse this call out of ourselves to ourselves (theย first self being the โthey-self โ and the second, the authentic self), as a morbid introspection. Such an obsession with ourselves is just one more vivid expression of the
domination of the They. On the contrary, the call to be ourselves is the recognition of ourselves as Being-in-the-world. What the call calls me to be, from within myself, is to own my possibilities rather than to live them through the vicarious imprimatur of the They. Even with this change of attitude, I am still occupied with the business of the world through my everyday relations to things and others. What has changed is only how I relate to them. Rather than they owning me, I own them. Such an owning is not a possessing, but freeing them to be what they are. A hammer is free to be a hammer because I release it for this possibility. And I care for others only to the extent that I free them for their own possibilities rather than take them over.
Neither the caller nor what is called is anything distinct or definite. I am not called to be or do anything. Such definite possibilities are pre- cisely how the They calls. Rather I am appealed to silently from within myself out of my lostness in the world. It is the very indis- tinctness and indefiniteness of this call which breaks through the โidle chatterโ. If the call, as Heidegger writes, โcomes from out of me and beyond meโ, then I should not interpret this as a voice which speaks to me from outside (the voice of God, for example) (BT: 320). Rather it โspeaksโ from the very depths of Daseinโs Being. It marks Daseinโs unease with himself (him โnot being at homeโ with himself which Heidegger described in anxiety). Such a disquiet is not psychological but ontological. It belongs to the very structure of Daseinโs Being that he is not at home, no matter how hard he tries to be so, in the world. Such โnot being at homeโ which belongs essentially to Daseinโs Being, is what Heidegger means by guilt in sectionย fifty-eight (BT: 325โ35). In German, guilt (Schuldย ) also means โdebtโ. Being in debt has a notion of being delivered over to something, as when I say I am in debt to someone. The debt Heidegger is referring to here is onto- logical. Daseinโs debt to his Being, so to speak, is its thrownness. I am delivered over to an existence whose origin I cannot get back behind. In this way, I am responsible, in being myself, for what is โnot meโ. My indebtedness (which is another way of speaking about my facticity) is revealed to me by anxiety, but what is disclosed here is understood as a possibility. Thus, what I am is not behind but before me. I am not only responsible for my existence as what I have โnot yetโ become, but what I have been as ahead of me. Being guilty, in this sense, for Heidegger, is being responsible for a double nothingness which lies at
the heart of my existence, or as he describes it, โBeing the null basis of a nullityโ (BT: 329).51ย I am not responsible for what is โnot meโ and what is โnot yetโ, thrownness and projection. It is exactly this noth- ingness which is covered over by my occupation by the everyday world, such that I understand myself only in terms of the possibilities which are given to me asย fixed and permanent, and not as the null ground of these possibilities as the โnotโ of thrown projection.
Although our everyday experiences must be the guide for our onto- logical analysis they should not determine it. Ordinarily, Heidegger points out in sectionย fifty-nine, conscience is understood as the weigh- ing up of good and bad actions or intentions (BT: 335โ41).52ย Being guilty, in this case, happens after the deed. This is to reverse the correct temporality of Daseinโs Being. What is behind me is always before me. My Being is not a description of a state of affairs, but a project I have to perform (or fail to perform). Such a โperformanceโ has its basis in my own ability to be, and makes no judgement about this or that particular possibility as being good or bad.
This is why it is important we do not understand this nullity or nothingness at the heart of Daseinโs existence ontically. It is not because Dasein lacks some concrete possibility that it is guilty. Rather, only because ontologically speaking the basis of its Being is nothing can it have any concrete possibilities at all. Only if Dasein were all possibilities in the world would nothingness not be at the heart of exis- tence (in other words, if it were God). We know, however, that in choosing this or that possibility all other possibilities are not possible. What the call of conscience appeals to is Daseinโs recognition of its ownย finitude (โwanting to have a conscienceโ); what it really means to exist as a mortal being who understands it is mortal. Such an under- standing, which is a particular kind of authentic possibility, Heidegger calls, in section sixty, โresolutenessโ (Entschlossenheit), whose German intentionally recalls disclosure (Erschlossenheit) (BT: 341โ8).
Being resolute, I am open to the disclosure of my Being and I hold onto myself in this openness. Only out of this resoluteness can there be an authentic relation to things (concern) and others (solicitude). Again, resoluteness must be a possibility which is projected ahead of ourselves. Such a projection, Heidegger calls a โresolutionโ or โdeci- sionโ (Entschluร) (BT: 345). Most of the time we do not make a deci- sion about our lives, but just drift along, thinking and doing what
others think and do. Our Being only becomes an issue for us when we do make a stand upon who we are. This does not have to change what we are, and it certainly does not mean we cut ourselves offย from the world, but it does change how we relate to what we are. It transforms our reality from a mere succession of barely distinguishable events and occurrences, in which we are lost in our daily habits and rituals, into a โsituationโ (BT: 346). I am not resolute because there are situa- tions (dangerous, exciting or otherwise), but because I am resolute there are situations. Rather than accepting my possibilities asย fixed (as though they were actualities), I face them as possibilities and as my own. We might get confused about resoluteness and think it is about being certain, but I think it is quite the opposite. It is about being absolutely unsure about our existence and this is what it means to live in the possible, rather than the actual.
The purpose of theย first and second chapters of division two ofย Being and Timeย is to show that Daseinโs Being as a whole can be under- stood and it is possible for an individual Dasein to do so. Heidegger believes he has demonstrated this by showing that authentic existence is possible. What is still not clear, however, is how this way of Being of Dasein is a clue to the meaning of Being in general, which we know is the general aim of the book. This will only become so when we understand how the unity of the structure of care is achieved through temporality. Such an accomplishment will be the object of our dis- cussion in the following andย final part.
Time and History
Heidegger makes it clear that the whole of chapter three of division two is a repetition of the analytic of Dasein, but now through the analysis of time (BT: 352). I do not think it is necessary, for our expla- nation, to go through the argument in the extraordinary detail that he does, but merely to capture the essence of what is being discussed (in fact, the last three chapters are almost a summary of the whole of the argument ofย Being and Time). As we noted at the end of the last part, what is of primary concern to us here is how Heidegger re- interprets the structure of Daseinโs Being in terms of time. Unlike our previous exposition, we shall make no attempt to explain each section, but only follow the central themes as they move from one section to
the next and across the chapters. It is certainly the case that none of this analysis should surprise us, since Heidegger has already, through- outย Being and Time, spoken of the three parts of the structure of care (facticity, existence and fallenness) by way of time. He does so now, however, explicitly.
What is significant to them all is the difference between existential time (we might say โlived timeโ, as long as this is not misunderstood as a series of experiences) and clock or calendar time. The former is the ontological basis of the latter, and the relation between the future, present and past in existential time is quite different from our common sense conception of time which Heidegger describes in the last chapter. Between theย first and last chapters, Heidegger applies existential time to a specific problem: how do we exist historically? The answer to this question demonstrates more vividly how Dasein exists temporally, and why this should be not confused with the meta- physical conception of time as a series of now points arising one after the other. The order of Heideggerโs argument is as follows: scientific time has its basis in our ordinary experience of time which has its source in the Being of Dasein. Our exposition follows this order and this part is divided into three sections: โInauthentic Temporalityโ, โAuthentic Temporalityโ and โHistoryโ. The presentation of the argu- ment inย Being and Time, however, is the other way around and begins with the temporality of Dasein. This is because the overall aim of the work is to show that the Being of Dasein is the clue to the meaning of Being in general. We have turned the order around because it better agrees with the phenomenological explanation which must begin with our everyday experience and then the birth of our meta- physical and scientific image of time from there.53
Inauthentic Temporality
Possibly if someone were to ask us about time, we would think that it was some kind of mysterious physical substance (in the same way that we might think of space), that things were in and that this substance could be measured by instruments. And we might even believe we would understand the nature of time better the more accurate these instruments were. Yet, Time is not a property of things (like colour) but a way of Being. It is not an adjective but an adverb. We might already have a premonition of this meaning of time in our everyday
experience. Do we not feel sometimes that time is moving quickly when we are enjoying ourselves and are interested and very slowly when we are bored, and that this sensation has nothing to do with how fast the hands are moving around the clock (in fact sometimes we can be so bored they seem to moving backwards)? This does not mean time is merely a subjective phenomenon, if we mean by โsubjectiveโย fictional and illusory, since we really do live temporally, but it is not a physical property of the universe existing separately from us. The uni- verse is temporal because we are, and not the other way around.
In the language ofย Being and Time, we can say time is existential rather than categorical. But what does existential time look like? Another common way of looking at time is as a straight line. We think of ourselves now existing in the present, and this present disappears into a past which is no longer, then another now will appear from a future which is not yet, and so on endlessly. The more we think of time as a line, however, the more puzzling it might seem. For if we exist in the present how long is it? Does it not disappear as soon it exists? As soon as we say โnowโ it is no longer now and so on. Time then would appear to be nothing, but we do appear to experience the passing of time. The purpose of Heideggerโs analysis of time inย Being and Timeย is twofold:ย first, to show that Daseinโs Being is temporal, and second, that this temporality cannot be understood through this common sense image of time. Indeed this image of time has its origin in our ordinary experience of time which has its roots in Daseinโs temporal- ity. This does not mean that this image of time is false, but it is onto- logically derivative. Such an image of time might be useful for scientific experiments, but it is not how we experience time.
Time is not a succession of โnowsโ, as Heidegger argues in section eighty-one, but this is precisely how philosophers have always attempted to understand it (BT: 472โ80). Now this should not sur- prise us, since the history of philosophy has always covered over the distinctive nature of Daseinโs Being, because it has understood Being generally as a substance, as though all Being were the same as the Being of things present-to-hand. Within this history, the most impor- tant philosopher is Aristotle, with whom we have already noted Heidegger always has an ambivalent relationship, since Aristotle both opens up,ย first of all, the question of Being, and, at the same time, closes it down by initiating this metaphysics of substance. The same
in the case of time. Aristotle is the most important philosopher of time and determines how it is thought in philosophy right up until Hegel (indeed it is this metaphysics which nourishes the scientific image of time).
Here, turning to the lectures ofย The Basic Problems of Phenomenologyย can be a very useful supplement to our reading, because Heidegger gives his students a detailed reading of Aristotleโs description of time, which is absent fromย Being and Time.54ย It is not necessary for us to follow it in every detail, but a quick overview can show us what is involved in thinking of time as a succession of now points on a line and the prob- lems that might arise. For Aristotle, like his contemporaries, the expe- rience of time is inseparable from motion. Motion does not just mean movement, but also change; and this seems to be what we mean by time when we say something is at t1ย and has changed at t2. So at eleven oโclock the water was frozen, and thirty minutes later it was liquid because of the heat applied to it. When something changes, we do not think the change is outside it. Rather, it is the changing thing which changes and nothing else. Time, on the other hand, does not belong to the changing thing. It is everywhere, and yet at the same time, Aristotle says, and it is โalongsideโ the thing, otherwise how would we be able to say something changes through time? Time cannot be the same as change, as others before Aristotle had believed, but there can be no time without it. The function of time is to count change, just as we used it in ourย first example: t1, t2. t3, until infinity. Time is just this numbering: 1, 2, 3 . . . Time is not change and change is not time, but we encounter time in change when we count. This counting does not exist in the world, but is an activity of the human soul. It is because we count that we have an experience of time. We can say, โNow1, now2, now3โ, and so on, until infinity. Time, then, is just the measurement of change in the broadest sense.
When we come to look, however, at Aristotleโs explanation of the experience of time in more detail, more and more problems seem to emerge. Why should we think of time in this way? Heidegger focuses on a particular part of Aristotleโs definition, namely that the count- ing of time takes place within โthe horizon of the earlier and laterโ.55ย If we imagine time as a line on which we count points, then each point is earlier or later, or before or after, other points on the line. Even t1ย is before the moment of counting, and t2ย is after, and so on. But are not
โbeforeโ and โafterโ, โearlierโ and โlaterโ temporal terms, and where do they come from? The counting of time seems to be dependent on them, but they themselves have nothing to do with counting. They are experiences of time and not the counting of numbers. This brings us back to the argument ofย Being and Time. The common sense or scientific image of time as a succession of now points is dependent on our everyday experience of time which is not linear at all. It smuggles in this everyday experience without drawing attention to it, constructs an image of time from it, and then explains our everyday experience with the image of time rather than the other way around.
Heideggerโs distinctions are very subtle here, so it is worth paying attention to them. He is not saying that the conception of time as a line is false, but it involves an ontological horizon which it leaves in the dark. Such a horizon is our own experience of time. In a limited way, this is already visible in Aristotleโs text, when he says the count- ing of time in relation to change is an activity of the human soul, but his notion of activity is very limited here, and the image equally so. What Heidegger shows is that there is more involved in counting โnowsโ than Aristotle makes out. It is not just an experience of number but time. This is because when we experience time we experience a process or a transition. Even in the limited example of change, I do not just count up the changes of place, but experience the movement from one place to the next. If I did not retain the previous place, and expect the next, then I would have no experience of change at all. I can only say โnow thereโ, Heidegger points out, because I retain the previous โnowโ and expect the next one. All of this, he adds, I assume when I look at my watch or a clock on the wall, and say, โNow it is twenty minutes past three.โ56ย This appears the give the โnowโ more thickness than is initially implied by to limited image of the time line. Every now point both refers to a โno longerโ and a โnot yetโ. But what gives this time this dilation and stretch?
Why do we have clocks? Does time matter to us because we have
clocks, or do we have clocks because time matters to us? Surely it is the latter and not the former? The only way toย find out the meaning of time is through Daseinโs involvement in the world. There are not any โnowsโ in the universe, rather we measure change through time because it is useful for us. The restricted image of time has its birth place in our more ordinary day-to-day experience of the world. Such
an origin is visible in the fact that even this limited image of time has to use the time-determinations โbeforeโ and โafterโ, โearlierโ and โlaterโ. There is time because we use time, and the use of time must have origin in the temporality of Dasein. Heideggerโs argument here is exactly the same as his displacement of the primacy given to scientific and theoretical reasoning elsewhere inย Being and Time. Rather than interpreting our pragmatic involvement with things in the world through cognition (present-to-hand), we should interpret cognition through involvement (ready-to-hand). Likewise, rather than under- standing time through clocks, we should understand clocks through our use of time.
Inย The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, Heidegger gives a wonderful phenomenological description of clocks and the telling the time, but at this point I want to return to our reading ofย Being and Time.57ย Again we need to remind ourselves that we are reading these chapters back- wards. Heideggerโs argument is from authentic temporality, to โworld timeโ or practical time, and thenย finally to scientific or metaphysical time. We, however, are going the other way, as he does in these later lectures. What, then, inย Being and Time, does Heidegger say about the derivation of clock time? To answer this question we need to read sec- tions seventy-nine to eighty-one (BT: 458โ80). Why do I need to ask you what time it is? Why do I have a clock or watch, or have the time permanently displayed on the taskbar at the bottom of my computer screen?58ย I must have all these ways of telling time, because they serve some kind of purpose or function. Now we have already come across this idea of function before and that is in the description of equip- ment.59ย Things only have a function because theyย fit into an activity of Dasein (an โin order toโ), and such activities only have a unity because of the overall significance of the world. If we are to make sense of clock time, therefore, we have to place it within the context of โworld timeโ.60
We tell the time because time matters to us. What Heidegger says is we โreckonโ with time. What he means by โreckoningโ is not the counting that Aristotle describes, but something far more pragmatic. I assign things a time because they are important to me. This time might be movement of the sun across the sky (which is almost para- digmatic for Heidegger: โThe sun dates the time which is interpreted in concernโ [BT: 413]), or a change of the seasons or of the hands of
a clock, but what matters to me is the assignation. Tomorrow, I have to go to the office, late summer is the time for making hay, there is a meeting at 3 p.m. which I cannot miss. What we notice about all these assignations, which are part of my reckoning with time, is that they all have a certain time no matter how long their duration. Heidegger calls this โdatabilityโ (Datierbarkeit). It is this โdatabilityโ which is the true origin of time as a series of nows. I think of each significant assign- ment of time as a particular โthenโ and it is this โthenโ which becomes reified into a infinite series of nows. The pragmatic origin of the metaphysical view of time is only visible through the โbeforeโ and โafterโ and โearlierโ and โlaterโ. Being โnowโ is not a property of a thing, but a โmaking presentโ or โenpresentingโ (Gegewรคrtigen) in relation to Dasein. If we are to understand the time of things, clocks or calen- dars, then we can only do so through Daseinโs ability to make things present. But this making present can only be made sense of through time as a whole. Making present is significant only in relation to the past and the future as it is experienced by Dasein. So the reason that โbeforeโ and โafterโ, โearlierโ and โlaterโ are implicit to time, and every now point is stretched between a โno longerโ and the โnot yetโ, is not because of a strange property of time as some kind of mysterious sub- stance which things are in, but because the Being of Dasein is tem- poral. Why, then, do we end up interpreting time as though it were a line of nows? We already know the answer to this question. For the most part, Dasein understands itself through its everyday experience of the world (fallenness). I am so involved with things in the world that I interpret myself as they are rather than what I am. It is this inau- thentic temporality which has become the source of our metaphysi- cal image time, which is then reinforced by its legitimation as it passes down through the history of Western philosophy, such that we are now certain that it is the scientific measurement of time which is true and our own experience of time false. This is not a matter, as we have already underlined, of replacing an objective with a subjective view- point, but of uncovering the ontological ground which is prior to this distinction and which is Daseinโs Being.
Authentic Temporality
Time is not a substance, but a way of Being, and more specifically a way in which Dasein is. I am not in the past, present and future, rather
I am my past, present and future. We have to understand this existen- tial time very differently from categorical time. It is, for example, ori- entated towards the present, whereas existential time is directed towards the future. We shall see this changes fundamentally how we think about the unity of time itself. As we now know, categorical time has its origin in the experience of everyday time or world time. But it has its basis there in a very particular way. Categorical time is an off-ย shoot of inauthentic existence or fallenness. It is this inauthentic tem- porality which Heidegger describes in the fourth chapter, โTemporality and Everydaynessโ (BT: 383โ423). Authentic existence is not the oppo- site of inauthentic existence, but comes from it. It is, to use Heideggerโs language, a modification of inauthentic existence, but in describing authentic existence we see what the ontological roots of both are. We might think of categorical time as the ossification of inauthentic tem- porality (hardening the present into narrowing of the now), whereas authentic temporality is its dissolving (through the freedom of the future whose ultimate possibility is the nothingness of death). In the former, I lose myself in my absorption in my concern about things, whereas in the latter, I come back to myself through anxiety. What Iย find there, as we saw from the previous part, is not something, but lit- erally no-thing. It is the โnothingโ which liberates me from the tyranny of things and the stiffening of actuality. Time might be the great destroyer, but what it gives to Dasein is its ultimate freedom and meaning.
How then do I experience the everyday time of care? First of all
what matters to me is the present. Not of course as a now point on a line, but in terms of what I am busying myself with. This might be what I am going to do in the next hour, or in twenty yearsโ time, but what is common to them both is that I am taken over by my real or imagined actualities. Rather than my being the source of my life, my life seems to be source of me. I feel trapped and alienated by what I do. My occu- pations occupy me and my daily lifeย flows along like the famous image of the river of time. In being busy with the present in this sense, the past only appears as something to be retained andย finally forgotten when it no longer matters, and the future only expected in relation to what is required and needed. It is this time which holds together the continuity of my everyday world. I expect things to be how I remem- ber them. Everyday life is a ritual glued together by time. This is the
real meaning of the transcendence of the world. As we remember from earlier, the world is not a thing in which I am contained like water in a glass.61ย The world is not a being, but the way in which Dasein is. Because Dasein exists temporally, then the world too is temporal. The world is a form of time, its consistency and familiarity.
But just as my life can be lived as fallen, and for the most part it is, where all that concerns me disappears into idle talk, curiosity and ambiguity, and time is just the next moment disappearing into a past already forgotten and a future yet jaded, then I can also be authentic, which means facing my possibilities as my own. This too must be thought temporally. I can only be these possibilities because there is another way of Being in time. If inauthentic time orientates itself in the present, then authentic temporality is fundamentally directed towards the future.
Such a trajectory is already visible in Daseinโs own existence. Heidegger defines existence, as we know, as possibility.62ย I am my pos- sibilities. A stone is what it is, but I am what I am not. Not through a simple negation or destruction, but because I can project myself ahead of myself. Such a projection is not a simple plan or project, for this is the future of inauthentic time: merely waiting or expecting something in relation to what I decide or want. As Mulhall writes, projection is not an activity, but something I am.63ย I do not decide to be in the future, rather I am my future. This is what is disclosed to me in my understanding. It is the future which makes the possible possi- ble, not the possible the future. If Dasein were not already in the future, then there could be no possibilities. I, like the stone, would be just carried along by time outside of it.
We know from our reading ofย Being and Timeย that Dasein does not just exist through its understanding but also in its moods.64ย How does Dasein live through its moods temporally? Moods are what reveal my world as the past. In German, โI have beenโ is โIch bin gewesenโ, literally, โI am beenโ. The past is not something which has gone and is lost forever in the next moment, rather I am my past. The past is some- thing which lives through me and in which I live. Just as what is pos- sible is only so through the future, then facticity and thrownness (the fact that I exist already in a world which precedes me) is only made possible by the past. Without the past the world could not weigh upon me. Temporally, then, moods belong to the past.65
I can be in a mood inauthentically or authentically, and the two illustrations Heidegger uses here are already familiar to us: fear and anxiety (BT: 389โ96). From initial viewing, fear would seem to be a poor example to illustrate the pastness of moods, since am I not afraid of what comes to me from out of the future? But what is it exactly that I fear when I am afraid of something? I fear for myself and more pre- cisely the world in which I already live. I fear theย flood because it will wash away this world, the world I have been thrown into and not some future one. Such a fear does not, however, reveal the pastness of the world, even though it springs from it, because I am so occupied with the present that I cannot see it. All that matters to me, quite naturally, is saving my own possessions, my wardrobe as itย floats past my window. It is anxiety, on the contrary, that reveals to me the totality of my existence, but it only does so by separating me from the present of my concern.
Only with anxiety can we see for theย first time what an authentic, as opposed to an inauthentic, temporality might be. In inauthentic time, it is the present or โmaking presentโ which is central, and the past and the future are orientated towards this endeavour (the metaphysi- cal and scientific image of time as a succession of now points is a pale reflection of this ordinary everyday time). In authentic temporality, on the contrary, it is the future towards which the unity of time is directed. I live my past and my present through the future, rather than my past and future through the present. This gives a completely differentย flow to existence. It means the past is not something which was and the future just what will be (a โno longerโ and a โnot yetโ), but what I come to be through the future (or it comes towards me out of the future) and this future past is what I experience in the present. This present, which is the result of this movement of the โfuture pastโ, is quite different from the present of inauthentic time. Heidegger, bor- rowing this phrase from Kierkegaard, in order to distinguish it from the inauthentic present of keeping busy calls it, a โmoment of visionโ (Augenblick) (BT: 387). If in everyday concern, I lose myself in theย flow of time, then in this โmoment of visionโ (which comes to me through anxiety), I am thrown back upon myself. This is why authenticity is not an empty projection into the future, but always determined by our past. We come to our past authentically as a possibility of our future and we take up what we already were. Such an authentic relation to
the past, Heidegger calls โrepetitionโ, as opposed to the inauthentic relation, which he calls โforgettingโ.
We have now seen that the structure of care is temporal. Existence is the future, facticity is the past, and fallenness is the present. We have also seen that time can be temporalised in two ways: authentically and inauthentically. In theย first, the present is primary, and in the second, the future. Yet, as Heidegger has already said at the beginning of divi- sion two, it is not enough just to describe what Dasein is from the outside, but we have to ask ourselves if it is possible for Dasein to be like this at all. Such an attestation is only given through Being- towards-death (BT: 274โ8). Ourย final question in this section, there- fore, has to be what is the relation between death and time?
To answer this question we have to go back to where Heidegger begins, chapter three: โDaseinโs Authentic Potentiality-for-Being-a- Whole, and Temporality as the Ontological Meaning of Careโ (BT: 349โ82). At the beginning of this chapter, Heidegger asks himself whether he has only arbitrarily stuck resoluteness and Being-towards- death together. Why should death be the ultimate future through which all my other futures must be weighed? Cannot it be that I could be equally resolute about other possibilities? No, because the future possibility of death is very different from all other possibilities and so only it can call me to be resolute. It is for this very reason that I shy away from it and busy myself with the world. It is death, in other words, which allows me to make the distinction between authentic and inauthentic temporality, between future which is mine and the future which belongs to everyone indifferently.
The future possibility of my death differs from any other possibil- ity because it reveals my life as a whole, rather than just parts of it. Whenever I am occupied with something, itย fills my attention. I lose myself when I am involved and absorbed in the world. When, however, I am anxious of my death, then my whole life is visible to me in a moment. I ask myself, โWhy I am doing this? โHow did I get into this situation?โ I am not asking about this or that activity or occupa- tion, but the significance of my life as a whole. These are very different questions. In theย first, I identify myself with partial realities, my profession, status or role in life. In the second, I see all these are substitutes for the ultimate meaning. Not that this question tells me what I ought to do (it is precisely this kind of moralising Heidegger
avoids). On the contrary, it shows me I am nothing and not identifiable with any of these. It is only because I am not so that I can choose authentically to individually have a profession, status or role. It is only the future possibility of death which shocks me into this insight, because as a possibility it is the possibility of my impossibility. Only this future is mine, because no one can die my death for me. All my other futures could be someone elseโs. Whatever I do, someone could equally do in my place. When Heidegger writes that Dasein โshattersโ itself against death it is not a celebration of morbidity, but the freeing of my possibilities (BT: 437). For theย first time I own what I have become in all itsย finitude.
Only through the anticipation of my future death can I choose myself. Thus resoluteness and anticipation are not wilfully pushed together, but theย first is part of the second. If you face your death as yours, then you will choose your existence individually rather than have it chosen for you by the They. But why is this future more future than any other? Being towards death is only authentic if I relate to my death as a possibility and not as an actuality. It is not my future as something which will happen at a definite time (something I can always, therefore, put off), but an indefinite future. Being-towards-death is a permanent possibility of my life, not an actuality which ends it. It is upon this indefinite future that all my definite futures are projected, and it shows them all as inherently fragile and insubstantial. This is the real truth of humanย finitude. Not that we are not God, or even that God is dead, but our existence is without solid ground. We are ciphers you and I, and our masks only hide the nothingness beneath them.
History
If Dasein is essential futural, this does mean its history is of no inter- est to it, but we do have to think of it in a different way. To some degree this chapter (โTemporality and Historicalityโ) is itself a histor- ical curiosity, and Heidegger (unlike the rest ofย Being and Time) is involved in a local quarrel which we ourselves might not be aware of (BT: 424โ55).66ย None the less, I do think it gives us some idea of the practical application of authentic temporality to a specific problem. What are we doing when we do history? Are there historical facts? Can history be treated as a science? Is there even anything objective about history, or is it only a story we tell ourselves?
It should not astonish us by now that Heidegger is going to dismiss out of hand that history is a science. But this does not mean it is merely โsubjectiveโ, if you understand by this untrue and relative. On the contrary, if we understand history ontologically, then it is more true than any objective science, because it expresses the way Dasein is. Science comes out of our history. It does not fall from the skies like the meteors which it observes. What does it mean, then, to think about history ontologically? First of all, we have to reject the naive idea that history is just about events which have happened in the past. For why would these events be any more significant than any other? This is not deny these events have happened (no more than it is to deny that the sun would exist if the human race were to end), but they only have a significance because they mean something for us now.
Heideggerโs approach, as always, is phenomenological. He asks us (in section seventy-three) to think about an object in a museum (BT: 429โ34). What makes this object something which belongs to the past? Is it a property like redness or hardness? But anything that I could say about something past, I could also say about something I am using now. Even if I say it is worn down and broken, then there are things in the present which are too. No, the reason I experience this tool in the museum as something which belongs to the past is because it was part of a world which is no longer present. It belongs to Ancient Greece, for example, because such a world existed. Now the world, as we know, is not an objective property of things, but their ontological condition. Things have a meaning because they belong to a world. The world is their general significance. Such significance has its origin in the Being of Dasein. It is only because Dasein is a being which can have a world that there is a world in theย first place and that this world is historical. I do not have a past, because I exist in history, but there is history because I have a past.
But why is the past world of the tool I now see lying in the museum of any importance to me? Only because the past belongs to me in the present. If we are to understand history properly, that is to say, ontologically, then we have to understand it through the temporal- ity of Dasein. We have already seen that the past is not just a โno longerโ in which every present now disappears as soon as it comes out of the โnot yetโ of the future. I am my past as my present. But
this means I can be my history authentically, just as I can the rest of my existence. From this it follows that my history must be under- stood in terms of my future. Why do I go into the museum to look at tools of the Ancient Greeks? Because such a understanding belongs to my future projection. Of course, I can go into the museum just to pass the time or because I think this is what educated people should do, yet I can also go there to understand myself, and this is the authentic root of any history. Facts matter because they matter to us in our self-understanding and not just because they have happened. It is perfectly conceivable that at some future date the history of the Ancient Greeks will not matter, but not to those who take the Western tradition seriously, since as Heidegger will show in his writing afterย Being and Time, their decisions have been fateful to our own.67
There are two possible relations to history, which mirrors our own experience of the past. Either it is immediately forgotten as it is con- sumed, or it is repeated as a future possibility. The ontological basis of history is, therefore, repetition. Not as an actuality (which is why there is always something vaguely comic about re-enactments), but as a future possibility. Looked at from this perspective, the Fall of the Bastille did not just happen once on 14 July 1789, but again and again, and it is these repetitions which make theย first event significant, not the other way around. The time of history, therefore, is closer to the festival than clock time. The past belongs to me more than any historical text book or a programme on the television, but if I did not exist in the past in this way and have a sense of my continuity with it (a โlifeโ, as Heidegger would say, stretched bet- ween birth and death [BT: 425โ7]), then none of this would inter- est me at all. It is because Dasein is thrown into a world that it is historical (a being which has a past). It is not thrown because it is historical.
Just as much as history can be significant for the individual (โfatefulโ in Heideggerโs language), then it can also be so for a people, race or country. A people can only have a destiny because it repeats its past in an authentic manner; that is, it grasps the future which is pregnant there. At this moment, Heidegger seems to imply there can be authentic community which is not the same as the They. These pas- sages also have an uncomfortable tone after the fact. Who cannot but
think of Germanyโs catastrophe when reading the following about the fate and destiny of a people; and there is no doubt that Heidegger was seduced by the Nazis.
Resoluteness implies handing oneself down by anticipation to โthereโ of the moment of vision; and this handing down we call โfateโ. This is also the ground for destiny, by which we understand Daseinโs historizing in Being- with-Others. (BT: 438)
Does the tragedy of Heideggerโs own politics (a tragedy to himself, as to a whole people, and one which we should never forget) render his ontology meaningless?ย Ad hominemย arguments have no place in phi- losophy. What is at issue is not just the meaning of history, but whether it should be theย final judge. What is lacking inย Being and Timeย is any ethics. Not ethics as anย ethos, or a calculative morality (which seem to be the only two ways Heidegger can think ethics), but one in which my existence, and the right to my existence is called into question by the other, who is not merely a means by which I can be authentic. Why should the death of the other be any less significant than my own, and why not perhaps even more so?
Notes
In the winter semester of 1929โ30, โThe Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitudeโ.
For the importance of Aristotle in the writing ofย Being and Time, seeย The Genesis of Heideggerโsย Being and Time, pp. 227โ308.
I shall explain this view of time in the section โInauthentic Temporalityโ,
pp. 84โ9.
A Guide to Heideggerโsย Being and Time, p. 16.
As Jean Grondin informs us, Heidegger had already discussed the nature of questioning in great detail in his lectures prior to writingย Being and Timeย (specifically inย Introduction to Phenomenological Researchย andย History of the Concept of Time: Prolegomenaย [2005]). See โWhy Reawaken the Question of Being?โ inย Heideggerโsย Being and Time:ย Critical Essays,
pp. 15โ31 (Polt 2005). This essay, as a whole, is an excellent explanation of the introduction toย Being and Time.
Heideggerโs own examples will only make sense to you if you under- stand that โscienceโ in German,ย die Wissenschaft, does not just mean the
physical sciences, such as biology and chemistry, but all forms of human knowledge, even what we would call the humanities.
Except when the science itself is in crisis (Heidegger gives one example amongst others, of Einsteinโs theory of relativity), when it increasingly has to face ontological questions, but then the scientist has to become a philosopher and it might be said the best scientists are (BT: 30).
Let me be clear here that I can perfectly imagine a scientist, who has been so indoctrinated by the scientific method, and has no understand- ing of philosophy at all, could live her life as though science were the answer to everything, even the meaning of her existence, but still this way of living is not itself scientific.
I will describe the overall structure ofย Being and Timeย at the end of this part, pp. 33โ4.
I will describe what Heidegger means by falling in the section โFalling and Anxietyโ, pp. 68โ73.
Heideggerโs early lectures give us some idea of the importance of religious language to the development of his philosophy. Seeย The Phenomenology of Religious Lifeย (2004). The experience of the early Christianity (as opposed to the metaphysics of theology) is also the inspi- ration of his re-interpretation of time.
For Heideggerโs own reading of Plato beforeย Being and Time, we need to read his lecturesย Platoโs Sophistย (1997).
This is the origin of Derridaโs famous method of deconstruction. For his own explanation of the term, see โLetter to a Japanese Friendโ inย Derrida and Difference, pp. 1โ5. For the best commentary on deconstruction, seeย The Ethics of Deconstructionย (Critchley 1999).
For Heideggerโs full-scale treatment of Kantโsย Critique, seeย Kant and the Problem of Metaphysicsย (1997).
I shall explain this shift from the present to the future in โAuthentic Temporalityโ, pp. 89โ94.
This is not entirely true. He did write a small essay called โTime and Beingโ, but it is not a replacement of the missing third division of part one. On the contrary, it precisely tells us why it is absent. See,ย On Time and Beingย (1972).
These questions go beyond the scope of a commentary, but are perhaps what Foucault was alluding to at the end ofย The Order of Things.
Again Levinas (the most important interrogator of Heideggerโs descrip- tion of human existence), will ask whether the otherโs existence is not
more important than my own. If this is so, would this not reverse the relation between ethics and ontology, such that ontology would have its source in ethics, and not ethics in ontology? For Levinasโ most sustained engagement withย Being and Time, seeย God, Death and Time.
In the lectures of the winter semester 1929โ30, Heidegger describes the
fundamental mood of our age as one of boredom. Seeย The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitudeย (1995).
Even here, however, we each have to face our death singularly, since no one can die my death for me. I will explain our relation to death in โBeing towards Deathโ, pp. 73โ9.
It is important to underline that Heidegger is not against science, but sci- entism. As he remarks at the end of this section, to question the ontolog- ical assumptions of science is not to criticise the empirical work of these sciences, as thoughย Being and Timeย were offering an alternative science (BT: 50). This is still the case in his later essays on the scientific world view (which he now calls โtechnologyโ), though what is at stake has become even more pressing. Seeย The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essaysย (1977).
In the section โExistenceโ, pp. 26โ30.
I think Dreyfus is right to translateย sein-beiย as โbeing-at-homeโ rather than โbeing alongsideโ, since โalongsideโ still has a sense of spatial relation of things, as one thing being next to another thing. Seeย Being-in-the-World,
pp. 44โ5.
Heidegger already introduces the language of care in these chapters, but it is only in chapter six, โCare as the Being of Daseinโ that he addresses it directly. We shall have to wait until then to explain it in more detail. See โBeing-towards-Deathโ, pp. 73โ9.
As I explained in the introduction, โPhenomenology inย Being and Timeโ,
pp. 12โ16.
Unless I become anxious that I am wasting my life, see โFalling and Anxietyโ, pp. 68โ73.
In Heideggerโs essay โThe Origin of the Work of Artโ, it is not the break- down of equipment which makes the world visible but art. Seeย Basic Writings, pp. 147โ87.
This is why Dreyfusโ critique of some of the extraordinary claims of AI and cognitive science is still important today. Seeย What Computers Still Canโt Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason.
Are Van Goghโs images of the stars inย Starry Nightsย (1889, Museum of Modern Art, New York) any less true than the pictures of the universe
made by the Hubble space telescope? Even if we say that one is truer than the other, this difference must have its source in ourselves. What we mean by the word โtruthโ will be the important focus of section forty- four ofย Being and Time, and indeed the rest of Heideggerโs career. I shall discuss truth in detail in โTruth and Realityโ, pp. 63โ6.
Such a de-severance of the world, rather than things in the world, is โvisualisedโ by Heidegger, in his later essays on technology, as โenfram- ingโ, where nature and human beings are reduced to resources to be used up. Such an negative meaning of equipment is only alluded to inย Being and Time, when for example, Heidegger refers to nature as mater- ial for work: โThe wood is a forest of timber, the mountain a quarry of rock; the river is water-power, the wind is wind โin the sailsโ โ (BT: 100). He does distinguish this nature from landscape which โenthrals usโ, but makes little of this distinction. For a good introduction to Heideggerโs thought afterย Being and Time, see J. Youngโsย Heideggerโs Later Philosophy.
In his bookย Being-in-the-World.
It is remarkable that in Descartesโย Meditationsย others appear as automa- tons that I cannot really be sure are human like me. See,ย Philosophical Writings of Descartes, p. 21.
See, for example, the important essay, โThe Essence of Truthโ which was written just afterย Being and Time. Heidegger inย Basic Writings,
pp. 115โ38.
This levelling down of possibilities Heidegger calls โpublicnessโ (รffentlichkeit) (BT: 165), but we might wonder if there is a more positive way of understanding the public world, as for example by his student, Hannah Arendt. Seeย The Human Condition.
In the section, โDescartes and Spatialityโ, pp. 46โ51.
Heideggerโs expression for moods,ย Befindlichkeit, derives from the German expression โWie befinden sich Sie?โ, which means โHow are you?โ or โHow do you feel?โ It is perhaps unfortunate that the translators ofย Being and Timeย translate it as โstate-of-mindโ, which gives it a far too cog- nitivistย flavour (BT: 172). Dreyfusโ translation โaffectednessโ is perhaps better. Seeย Being-in-the-World, pp. 168โ83.
In the section โExistenceโ, pp. 26โ30.
In the Introduction at the opening of the section โPhenomenology in
Being and Timeโ, p. 12.
This past is historical through and through, as Heidegger describes in the last sentences of the section on the understanding (BT: 194). We
have to wait until the end ofย Being and Timeย for the complete investiga- tion of history from an ontological perspective. See โHistoryโ, pp. 94โ6.
In the section, โMinenessโ, pp. 35โ9.
History of the Concept of Timeย (1985), pp. 260โ1.
The structure of this ontological hermeneutics is crucial to Gadamerโsย Truth and Method. Heidegger describes the implications of this hermeneutics on his own project at the end ofย Being and Timeย (BT: 358โ64).
This is the point of Wittgensteinโs famous story about the lion. See
Philosophical Investigations, p. 190.
In the section โFalling and Anxietyโ, pp. 68โ73.
He is careful to underline that we should not take such a reference to be an example of โword mysticismโ (BT: 262). It is because the word says something about the experience of truth, which is phenomenologically attested, that it is significant and not just because the Greeks used it. He stresses the same point in his earlier lectures on Aristotle given in the winter semester 1921โ2. Seeย Phenomenological Interpretations of Aristotleย (2001), p. 93.
I explained the meaning of โde-severanceโ in Chapter Two, in the section โDescartes and Spatialityโ, pp. 46โ51.
I am thinking here, of course, of Heideggerโs infamous seduction by the Nazi party. Safranskiโs biography is an excellent guide to what actually did and did not happen at this time in Heideggerโs life. Seeย Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil, pp. 225โ47.
The importance of nothing to the understanding of Being is further rein- forced by Heidegger in a lecture he gave just after the publication ofย Being and Time, โWhat is Metaphysics?โ Seeย Basic Writingsย (1994), pp. 93โ110.
Blanchot and Levinas reverse this phrase and speak not of death as the possibility of impossibility, but as the impossibility of possibility. Even in Heideggerโs analysis, is there not an avoidance of some of the pain and distress of dying? What is important for him is the existential courage in the face of the possibility of death in which I choose to be who I am, but does not dying also strip me of all my power to do just this? See Blanchotโsย The Space of Literature, pp. 87โ108.
I explained the meaning of discourse in โMoods, Understanding and
Languageโ, pp. 56โ63.
I have slightly changed the English translation here so as to be closer to the German:ย dasย (nichtige)ย Grund-sein einer Nichtigkeit.
This is another place inย Being and Timeย where Heidegger dismisses ethics. We might be (like Magda King) a little more suspicious of this manoeu- vre, since he appears to understand it as only calculative. See Kingโsย A Guide to Heideggerโsย Being and Time, pp. 169โ70.
Interestingly enough, this is also the order of Heideggerโs explanation of time inย The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, which were lectures that he gave just after the publication ofย Being and Timeย in 1927. These lectures are the most important commentary on this part of the book and should be read alongside it. Seeย The Basic Problems of Phenomenologyย (1982),
pp. 227โ330.
The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, pp. 231โ56.
Ibid. p. 240.
Ibid. p. 245.
Ibid. pp. 257โ61. He also discusses clock time in theย Zollikon Seminars, which is a good introduction to this thought, because here he is speaking to psychiatrists rather than philosophers, and therefore expects no prior knowledge or expertise. Seeย Zollikon Seminarsย (2001), pp. 28โ80.
Notice that this is a very different question from Aristotleโs. We are asking not, โWhat is time?โ, but, โWhy is there time?โ Questions involv- ing a โwhatโ tend to make us think we are talking about some kind of substance, and it is precisely this way of thinking about time that Heidegger is trying to move us away from.
In โWorldโ, pp. 39โ46.
What Heidegger means by โworld timeโ is not a time common to the world (such as Greenwich Mean Time) but the time belonging to Being- in-the-world.
In the section, โWorldโ, pp. 39โ46.
As I described in the section โExistenceโ, pp. 26โ30.
Routledge Philosophical Guidebook to Heidegger andย Being and Time, p. 149.
As I described in โMoods, Understanding and Languageโ, pp. 56โ63.
An excellent literary example here would be Proustโsย In Search of Lost Time, when the narrator bites into the madeleine and conjures up the past of his childhood (p. 47ff.) Is this not exactly what Heidegger means by a mood revealing the world to us? It does so always temporally through the past.
For an informative summary of this context, see Barashโs essay โHistorical Meaning in the Fundamental Ontology ofย Being and Timeโ, inย Heideggerโsย Being and Time: Critical Essaysย (Polt 2005), pp. 169โ88.
I am thinking here of Heideggerโs discussion of technology and its origin in Ancient Greek thought. The importance of the history of phi- losophy to philosophy follows from Heideggerโs conception of Being of Dasein. We cannot dismiss the past out of hand because it makes us what we are in the present, seeย The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essaysย (1977).